Philosophical Papers Volume II
Lewis (David)
This Page provides (where held) the Abstract of the above Book and those of all the Papers contained in it.
Colour-ConventionsDisclaimerBooks / Papers Citing this Book

BOOK ABSTRACT:

Cover Blurb

  1. This is the second collection of philosophical essays by David Lewis, one of the most innovative, influential, and important philosophers now writing in English. Consisting of thirteen papers in all, Philosophical Papers: Volume II includes both new essays and previously published papers, some of them with extensive new postscripts reflecting his current thinking.
  2. Volume I1 contains papers on ontology, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language. The papers in Volume II focus on causation2 and several other closely related topics, including counterfactual and indicative conditionals, the direction of time, subjective and objective probability explanation, perception, free will, and rational decision. Both this collection and its companion volume fit into Lewis's longtime advocacy of the thesis he calls "Humean supervenience3." Named after philosopher David Hume, the great denier of necessary connections, Humean supervenience4 posits that "all there is to the world is a vast mosaic of local matters of particular fact, just one little thing and then another." Throughout these papers, Lewis analyzes global features of the world in such a way as to show that they might turn out to supervene5 on the spatiotemporal arrangement of local qualities, and at the same time replies to philosophical arguments against Humean supervenience6.
  3. Lewis's thesis — the backbone of this volume — links nearly all the major topics addressed in his essays and establishes Philosophical Papers: Volume II as another of Lewis's major contributions to philosophy.



In-Page Footnotes ("Lewis (David) - Philosophical Papers Volume II")

Footnote 1: See "Lewis (David) - Philosophical Papers Volume I".



"Lewis (David) - Philosophical Papers Volume II: Introduction"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Introduction


Full Text
  1. Eleven of the papers in this volume were originally published from 1972 to 1981; misprints apart, they are reprinted in their original form. In some cases, where retractions or additions seemed urgently needed, I have appended postscripts. Two other papers appear here for the first time. The papers in this volume deal with topics concerning counterfactuals, causation1, and related matters. Papers in ontology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language have appeared in "Lewis (David) - Philosophical Papers Volume I". I have left out papers which are rejoinders, or which are of primarily technical interest, or which overlap too much with the papers I have included. Abstracts2 of the omitted papers may be found here, in the bibliography of my writings.
  2. Many of the papers, here and in Volume I, seem to me in hindsight to fall into place within a prolonged campaign on behalf of the thesis I call "Humean supervenience3." Explicit discussion of that thesis appears only in "Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance"; but it motivates much of the book.
  3. Humean supervenience4 is named in honor of the greater denier of necessary connections. It is the doctrine that all there is to the world is a vast mosaic of local matters of particular fact, just one little thing and then another. (But it is no part of the thesis that these local matters are mental.) We have geometry; a system of external relations of spatio-temporal distance between points. Maybe points of spacetime itself, maybe point-sized bits of matter or aether or fields, maybe both. And at those points we have local qualities: perfectly natural intrinsic properties which need nothing bigger than a point at which to be instantiated5. For short: we have an arrangement of qualities. And that is all. There is no difference without difference in the arrangement of qualities. All else supervenes6 on that.
  4. First say it, then qualify it. I don't really mean to say that no two possible worlds whatsoever differ in any way without differing in their arrangements of qualities. For I condede that Humean supervenience7 is at best a contingent truth. Two worlds might indeed differ only in unHumean ways, if one or both of them is a world where Humean supervenience8 fails. Perhaps there might be extra, irreducible external relations, besides the spatiotemporal ones; there might be emergent natural properties of more-than-point-sized things; there might be things that endure identically through time or space, and trace out loci that cut across all lines of qualitative continuity. It is not, alas, unintelligible that there might be suchlike rubbish. Some worlds have it. And when they do, it can make differences between worlds even if they match perfectly in their arrangements of qualities.
  5. But if there is suchlike rubbish, say I, then there would have to be extra natural properties or relations that are altogether alien to this world. Within the inner sphere of possibility, from which these alien intrusions are absent, there is indeed no difference of worlds without a difference in their arrangements of qualities9.
  6. Is this materialism? – no and yes. I take it that materialism is metaphysics built to endorse the truth and descriptive completeness of physics more or less as we know it; and it just might be that Humean supervenience10 is true, but our best physics is dead wrong in its inventory of the qualities. Maybe, but I doubt it. Most likely, if Humean supervenience11 is true at all, it is true in more or less the way that present physics would suggest.
  7. I have conceded that Humean supervenience12 is a contingent, therefore an empirical, issue. Then why should I, as philosopher rather than physics fan, care about it? Isn't my professional business more with the whole expanse of logical space than with the question which of its districts happens to be ours? – Fair enough. Really, what I uphold is not so much the truth of Humean supervenience13 as the tenability of it. If physics itself were to teach me that it is false, I wouldn't grieve.
  8. That might happen: maybe the lesson of Bell's theorem14 is exactly that there are physical entities which are unlocalized, and which might therefore make a difference between worlds – worlds in the inner sphere – that match perfectly in their arrangements of local qualities. Maybe so. I'm ready to believe it. But I am not ready to take lessons in ontology from quantum physics as it now is. First I must see how it looks when it is purified of instrumentalist frivolity, and dares to say something not just about pointer readings but about the constitution of the world; and when it is purified of doublethinking deviant logic; and – most of all – when it is purified of supernatural15 tales about the power of the observant mind to make things jump. If, after all that, it still teaches nonlocality, I shall submit willingly to the best of authority.
  9. What I want to fight are philosophical arguments against Humean supervenience16. When philosophers claim that one or another commonplace feature of the world cannot supervene17 on the arrangement of qualities, I make it my business to resist. Being a commonsensical fellow (except where unactualized possible worlds are concerned) I will seldom deny that the features in question exist. I grant their existence, and do my best to show how they can, after all, supervene18 on the arrangement of qualities. The plan of battle is as follows.
  10. First, laws of nature.
    • Few would deny that laws of nature, whatever else they may be, are at least exceptionless regularities. Not all regularities are laws, of course. But, following the lead of (a short temporal segment of) Ramsey, I suggest that the laws are the ones that buy into those systems of truths that achieve an unexcelled combination of simplicity and strength. That serves the Humean cause. For what it is to be simple and strong is safely noncontingent; and what regularities there are, or more generally what candidate systems of truths, seems to supervene19 safely on the arrangement of qualities. I stated such a theory of lawhood in my book "Lewis (David) - Counterfactuals" (1973), and here I discuss it further in Postscript C to "Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance".
    • I am prepared at this point to take the offensive against alleged unHumean lawmakers; I say there is no point believing in them, because they would be unfit for their work. Here I have in mind the theory that laws are made by a lawmaking second-order relation of universals20, a theory most fully presented by D. M. Armstrong21 in "Armstrong (David) - What is a Law of Nature?" (1983). Let N be the supposed lawmaker relation; the idea, in its simplest form, is that it is a contingent matter, and one not supervenient on the arrangement of qualities, which universals22 stand in the relation N; but it is somehow necessary that if N(F, G), then we have the regularity that all F's are G's. I ask: how can the alleged lawmaker impose a regularity? Why can't we have N(F, G), and still have Fs that are not G's? What prevents it? Don't try defining N in terms of there being a law and hence a regularity – we're trying to explain lawhood. And it's no good just giving the lawmaker a name that presupposes that somehow it does its stuff, as when Armstrong calls it "necessitation." If you find it hard to ask why there can't be F's that are not G's when F "necessitates" G, you should ask instead how any N can do what it must do to deserve that name.
  11. Next, counterfactuals. I take them to be governed by similarity of worlds, according to the analysis given in "Lewis (David) - Counterfactuals and Comparative Possibility", in this volume. To the extent that this similarity consists of perfect match in matters of particular fact, it .supervenes23 easily on the arrangement of qualities; and to the extent that it consists of (perfect or imperfect) conformity by one world to the laws of the other, it supervenes24 if the laws do. In "Lewis (David) - Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow", I argue that one important sort of counterfactual, at least, will work properly if it is governed by just these respects of similarity.
  12. Next, causation25. In "Lewis (David) - Causation" and its postscripts, I defend an analysis of causation26 in terms of counterfactual dependence between events. The counterfactuals are discussed here in the two papers just mentioned; and since counterfactual dependence only seems causal when it is between events, my treatment of causation27 requires "Lewis (David) - Events" before it is done. Causation28 draws the arrow from past to future; that arrow exists only as an asymmetric pattern in the arrangement of qualities, so causal counterfactuals must somehow be sensitive to the asymmetry. In "Lewis (David) - Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow" I offer an account of that sensitivity. Given causation29, or rather causal dependence, we can proceed to causal analyses of various things; for instance seeing, in "Lewis (David) - Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision", or what else you can do if you can freely raise your hand, in "Lewis (David) - Are We Free to Break the Laws".
  13. Next, persistence through time. I take the view that nothing endures identically through time. (Except universals30, if such there be; their loci would coincide with relations of qualitative match, would indeed constitute these relations, so they would commit no violations of Humean supervenience31.) Persisting particulars consist of temporal parts, united by various kinds of continuity. To the extent that the continuity is spatiotemporal and qualitative, of course it supervenes32 on the arrangement of qualities. But the continuity that often matters most is causal continuity: the thing stays more or less the same because of the way its later temporal parts depend causally for their existence and character on the ones just before. So the spatiotemporal boundaries of persisting things, for instance people, can supervene33 on the arrangement of qualities, provided that causation34 does. I discuss lines of causal continuity, not ruling out zigzag or broken lines, in "Lewis (David) - The Paradoxes of Time Travel". In "Lewis (David) - Survival and Identity", in Volume I of these Papers, I reply to some paradoxes brought against the idea that our survival is a matter of continuities that unite our temporal parts35.
  14. Next, mind and language. Several papers in the previous volume concern the thesis that mental states, indexed with content when appropriate, are definable as the occupants of causal roles. Some of these states are people's beliefs, and some of their beliefs are their expectations about other people. In "Lewis (David) - Convention" (1968) and in "Lewis (David) - Languages and Language" and "Lewis (David) - Radical Interpretation" in Volume I, I suggested how semantic facts could obtain in virtue of the mutual expectations that prevail in a linguistic community. And so it goes. There is room for endless argument over the details, but I remain confident that at every step mentioned the connection is something like what I have said – enough like it, anyway, to allow the cumulative Humean supervenience36 of one thing after another. At every step mentioned – but there is one that I passed over.
  15. There is one big bad bug: chance. It is here, and here alone, that I fear defeat. But if I'm beaten here, then the entire campaign goes kaput37. For chances enter at the very begining. A law, I said with Ramsey, is a regularity that enters into the best systems. But what sort of systems? If there are chances – single-case objective probabilities, for instance, that a certain atom will decay this week – then some regularities have to do with chances, and the best true systems will be those that do best, inter alia, at systematizing the truth about chances. So bestness of true systems, and hence lawhood, and hence counterfactuals and causation38 and occupancy of causal roles and all the rest, will not supervene39 just on the actual arrangement of qualities, but on that plus all the chances there are, at various times, of that arrangement continuing in one way or another. Therefore the only hope for Humean supervenience40 is that the chances themselves might somehow supervene41 on the arrangement of qualities.
  16. How could they? It is easy to go partway. The chances for alternative futures that obtain at a moment surely depend on just how things actually are at that moment. We might as well throw in the way things are at all previous times; that might help, and it's no harm including too much. So far, so good. We have a conditional: if history is so-and-so then the chances are such-and-such. And the antecedent of that conditional – history up to the moment in question – surely does supervene42 on the arrangement of qualities.
  17. But what is the status of the history-to-chance conditional itself? Is it necessary or contingent? If contingent, does it supervene43 or not on the arrangement of qualities?
  18. If history-to-chance conditionals are necessary truths, no worries. Then the chances at any moment supervene44 on the arrangement of qualities, in fact on just the part of it up to that moment. Sometimes, we can see how the conditional might be necessary: suppose it says that when we have prominent symmetry in the present set-up and its alternative futures, then those futures have equal chances. But sometimes not. How can an equality of chances based on symmetries, or any such necessary principle, give us the connections we need between, say, the exact height of a potential barrier and the exact chance of tunnelling through it? I hope there is a way, given the trouble I'm in if not; but I can't see what it is.
  19. If the conditionals are contingent, but themselves supervene45 on the arrangement of qualities, then again no worries. That would be so if they hold in virtue of relevant actual frequencies throughout the world, for instance. Or they could supervene46 in some fancier way, for instance by means of the "package deal" for chances and laws that I consider in Postscript C to "Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance". Alas, I fear it cannot be so. The trouble is that whatever pattern it is in the arrangement of qualities that makes the conditionals true will itself be something that has some chance of coming about, and some chance of not coming about. What happens if there is some chance of getting a pattern that would undermine that very chance? The Principal Principle of "Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance" affords a way of turning this vague worry into a proper argument; hence the dismal ending to that paper.
  20. Why not give in? I could admit that the history-to-chance conditionals, and so the chances themselves, are contingent and do not supervene47 on the arrangement of qualities. I could insist for consolation that at any rate all else supervenes48 on the arrangement of qualities and the chances together. Why not? I am not moved just by loyalty to my previous opinions. That answer works no better than the others. Here again the unHumean candidate for the job turns out to be unfit for its work. The distinctive thing about chances is their place in the 'Principal Principle,' which compellingly demands that we conform our credences about outcomes to our credences about their chances. Roughly, he who is certain the coin is fair must give equal credence to heads and tails; being less rough is the main business of "Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance". I can see, dimly, how it might be rational to conform my credences about outcomes to my credences about history, symmetries, and frequencies. I haven't the faintest notion how it might be rational to conform my credences about outcomes to my credences about some mysterious unHumean magnitude. Don't try to take the mystery away by saying that this unHumean magnitude is none other than chance! I say that I haven't the faintest notion how an unHumean magnitude can possibly do what it must do to deserve that name – namely, fit into the principle about rationality of credences – so don't just stipulate that it bears that name. Don't say: here's chance, now is it Humean or not? Ask: is there any way that any Humean magnitude could fill the chance-role? Is there any way that an unHumean magnitude could? What I fear is that the answer is "no" both times! Yet how can I reject the very idea of chance, when I know full well that each tritium atom has a certain chance of decaying at any moment49?
  21. [ … Acknowledgements … snip]




In-Page Footnotes ("Lewis (David) - Philosophical Papers Volume II: Introduction")

Footnote 2: These will be worth digging our sometime!

Footnote 5: Footnote 9: Footnote 14: See Wikipedia: Wikipedia: Bell's theorem.

Footnote 15: I’m glad to see Lewis takes this line! After all, mechanical observers collapse the wave function before a conscious mind looks at the printout.

Footnote 21: See also Footnote 35:
  • It is at this point that Humean supervenience has come under direct attack.
  • Saul Kripke, in "Identity through Time," given at the 1979 conference of the American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division, has argued that if a disk is made of homogeneous matter, then whether the disk is spinning or not is a feature of the world that does not supervene on the arrangement of qualities. We might have two worlds, just alike in their arrangements of qualities, one with a spinning disk and one with a stationary disk. (My "Humean supervenience" corresponds roughly to the "attenuated holographic hypothesis," which was one of Kripke's targets.) Whether the disk spins is, of course, definable in terms of the persistence of its parts through time; so in the first instance it is persistence that fails to supervene. But that might be because causation fails to supervene, and persistence requires causal continuity.
  • I reply by conceding, as I have, that Humean supervenience is contingent. The two worlds with their differing disks must (one or both) be worlds where there is something extra to make the difference. That does not show that any feature of this world fails to supervene on the arrangement of qualities. (Here I am indebted to Mark Johnston.)
Footnote 37: Oh dear! … and Lewis can’t see how he’s not beaten.

Footnote 49:
  • David Armstrong has pointed out (in discussion) that matters are still worse if we grant that chances may take extreme values, one or zero exactly. Let H specify some course of history up to a certain moment and let F specify some course of history after that moment. Assume that H and F are contingent. (We need not assume that they are maximally specific.) Let T be a history-to-chance conditional which says that after history H, the chance of F would be exactly one. To grant that chances may take extreme values is to grant that some such H and T might both hold. Then is there any possibility that H and T might hold without F? I say not. Any genuine possibility deserves at least some small share of credence, perhaps infinitesimal but not zero; but to give nonzero credence to this alleged possibility would violate the Principal Principle. So H and T strictly imply F. Now consider our three hypotheses about the status of history-to-chance conditionals.
    1. Are they noncontingent? If so, T is necessary, since ex hypothesi it is at least possible. Then H by itself strictly implies F. How can that be? What prevents us having H without F, when they specify the character of wholly distinct parts of the world? This necessary connection between distinct existences is unintelligible.
    2. Are they contingent, but supervenient on the arrangement of qualities? Then what would make T true is some pattern in the arrangement of qualities, and it is open to say that part of that pattern is simply that H does not hold or that F does. If so, we know how H and T can strictly imply F, so this second hypothesis gives no special problem about the case of extreme chances. But it still has its general problem: apart from the extreme case, how can a chancemaking pattern not give itself some chance of failing to obtain?
    3. Are they contingent, and not supervenient upon the arrangement of qualities? Then if T is true, there is some unHumean feature of the world that makes it true. Call this unHumean chancemaker X. Now X and H strictly imply F. How can that be? How could X manage to impose this constraint on the arrangement of qualities? If we reject strict implication of F by H alone, as we should, then we grant that there are arrangements of qualities which make H hold without F. How does X prevent us from having any of these arrangements? Compare this unHumean chancemaker with Armstrong's unHumean lawmaker, denounced above. Armstrong has a fair tu quoque against anyone who accepts the one and balks at the other. For the two are alike in their supposed power to constrain the course of events, except that one imposes a connection in the single case and the other imposes a general regularity. (Indeed, the chancemaker might just be the lawmaker at work in one particular instance.) Either way, it's unintelligible how the unHumean constrainer can possibly do its stuff.
  • None of these three alternatives seems at all good. The escape routes from the trilemma – doubting that chances really can take the extreme values, doubting that every genuine possibility deserves some slight credence, or doubting the Principal Principle – seem just as bad. But so far as I can see, we must choose one evil or another.



"Lewis (David) - Counterfactuals and Comparative Possibility"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 4: Counterfactuals and Time, Chapter 16



"Lewis (David) - Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 4: Counterfactuals and Time, Chapter 17

COMMENT: Printout filed in "Various - Papers on Logic & Metaphysics Boxes: Vol 2 (F-N)".



"Lewis (David) - The Paradoxes of Time Travel"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 4: Counterfactuals and Time, Chapter 18


Abstract
  1. This paper argues that time travel1 is possible, and that the paradoxes of time travel2 are oddities, not impossibilities.
  2. The defence of the possibility of time travel3 involves
    1. a commitment to enduring things having temporal as well as spatial parts,
    2. psychological continuity4 and connectedness and
    3. causal continuity
    as criteria of personal identity, and a distinction between external and personal time.

Author’s Introduction
  1. Time travel5, I maintain, is possible. The paradoxes of time travel6 are oddities, not impossibilities. They prove only this much, which few would have doubted: that a possible world where time travel7 took place would be a most strange world, different in fundamental ways from the world we think is ours.
  2. I shall be concerned here with the sort of time travel8 that is recounted in science fiction. Not all science fiction writers are clear-headed, to be sure, and inconsistent time travel9 stories have often been written. But some writers have thought the problems through with great care, and their stories are perfectly consistent.
  3. If I can defend the consistency of some science fiction stories of time travel10, then I suppose parallel defenses might be given of some controversial physical hypotheses, such as the hypothesis that time is circular or the hypothesis that there are particles that travel faster than light. But I shall not explore these parallels here.
  4. What is time travel11? Inevitably, it involves a discrepancy between time and time. Any traveler departs and then arrives at his destination; the time elapsed from departure to arrival (positive, or perhaps zero) is the duration of the journey. But if he is a time traveler12, the separation in time between departure and arrival does not equal the duration of his journey. He departs; he travels for an hour, let us say; then he arrives. The time he reaches is not the time one hour after his departure. It is later, if he has traveled toward the future; earlier, if he has traveled toward the past. If he has traveled far toward the past, it is earlier even than his departure. How can it be that the same two events, his departure and his arrival, are separated by two unequal amounts of time?


COMMENT:



"Lewis (David) - A Subjectivist's Guide to Objective Chance"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 5: Probability, Chapter 19



"Lewis (David) - Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional Probabilities"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 5: Probability, Chapter 20


Philosophers Index Abstract
    Ernest adams has noted that the assertability of indicative conditionals is measured by the conditional subjective probability of the consequent relative to the antecedent. I refute the suggestion that there is a way to interpret the conditional so that this conditional probability always equals the probability of the conditional itself; then I discuss the question of why the assertability of a conditional is not measured by its probability.


COMMENT: Printout filed in "Various - Papers on Logic & Metaphysics Boxes: Vol 2 (F-N)".



"Lewis (David) - Causation"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 6: Causation, Chapter 21


Author’s Introduction
  1. Hume defined causation1 twice over. He wrote "we may define a cause to be an object followed by another, and where all the objects, similar to the first, are followed by objects similar to the second. Or, in other words, where, if the first object had not been, the second never had existed."
  2. Descendants of Hume's first definition still dominate the philosophy of causation2: a causal succession is supposed to be a succession that instantiates a regularity. To be sure, there have been improvements. Nowadays we try to distinguish the regularities that count – the "causal laws" – from mere accidental regularities of succession. We subsume causes and effects under regularities by means of descriptions they satisfy, not by overall similarity. And we allow a cause to be only one indispensable part, not the whole, of the total situation that is followed by the effect in accordance with a law. In present-day regularity analyses, a cause is defined (roughly) as any member of any minimal set of actual conditions that are jointly sufficient, given the laws, for the existence of the effect.
  3. More precisely, …
  4. Much needs doing, and much has been done, to turn definitions like this one into defensible analyses. Many problems have been overcome. Others remain: in particular, regularity analyses tend to confuse causation3 itself with various other causal relations. If c belongs to a minimal set of conditions jointly sufficient for e, given the laws, then c may well be a genuine cause of e. But c might rather be an effect of e: one which could not, given the laws and some of the actual circumstances, have occurred otherwise than by being caused by e. Or c might be an epiphenomenon of the causal history of e: a more or less inefficacious effect of some genuine cause of e. Or c might be a preempted potential cause of e: something that did not cause e, but that would have done so in the absence of whatever really did cause e.
  5. It remains to be seen whether any regularity analysis can succeed in distinguishing genuine causes from effects, epiphenomena, and pre-empted potential causes – and whether it can succeed without falling victim to worse problems, without piling on the epicycles, and without departing from the fundamental idea that causation4 is instantiation of regularities. I have no proof that regularity analyses are beyond repair, nor any space to review the repairs that have been tried. Suffice it to say that the prospects look dark. I think it is time to give up and try something else.
  6. A promising alternative is not far to seek. Hume's "other words" – that if the cause had not been, the effect never had existed – are no mere restatement of his first definition. They propose something altogether different: a counterfactual analysis of causation5.
  7. The proposal has not been well received. True, we do know that causation6 has something or other to do with counterfactuals. We think of a cause as something that makes a difference, and the difference it makes must be a difference from what would have happened without it. Had it been absent, its effects – some of them, at least, and usually all – would have been absent as well. Yet it is one thing to mention these platitudes now and again, and another thing to rest an analysis on them. That has not seemed worthwhile. We have learned all too well that counterfactuals are ill understood, wherefore it did not seem that much understanding could be gained by using them to analyze causation7 or anything else. Pending a better understanding of counterfactuals, moreover, we had no way to fight seeming counterexamples to a counterfactual analysis.
  8. But counterfactuals need not remain ill understood, I claim, unless we cling to false preconceptions about what it would be like to understand them. Must an adequate understanding make no reference to unactualized possibilities? Must it assign sharply determinate truth conditions? Must it connect counterfactuals rigidly to covering laws? Then none will be forthcoming. So much the worse for those as statements about possible alternatives to the actual situation, somewhat vaguely specified, in which the actual laws may or may not remain intact? There are now several such treatments of counterfactuals, differing only in details. If they are right, then sound foundations have been laid for analyses that use counterfactuals.
  9. In this paper, I shall state a counterfactual analysis, not very different from Hume's second definition, of some sorts of causation8. Then I shall try to show how this analysis works to distinguish genuine causes from effects, epiphenomena, and preempted potential causes.


COMMENT:



"Lewis (David) - Causal Explanation"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 6: Causation, Chapter 22



"Lewis (David) - Events"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 6: Causation, Chapter 23



"Lewis (David) - Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 7: Dependence and Decision, Chapter 24



"Lewis (David) - Are We Free to Break the Laws"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 7: Dependence and Decision, Chapter 25

COMMENT: Annotated photocopy filed in "Various - Papers on Logic & Metaphysics Boxes: Vol 2 (F-N)".



"Lewis (David) - Prisoners' Dilemma is a Newcomb Problem"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 7: Dependence and Decision, Chapter 26


Author’s Introduction
  1. Several authors have observed that Prisoners' Dilemma and Newcomb's Problem are related – for instance, in that both involve controversial appeals to dominance.
  2. But to call them "related" is an under- statement. Considered as puzzles about rationality, or disagreements between two conceptions thereof, they are one and the same problem.
  3. Prisoners' Dilemma is a Newcomb Problem – or rather, two Newcomb Problems side by side, one per prisoner. Only the inessential trappings are different. Let us make them the same.

Author’s Conclusion
  1. Some have fended off the lessons of Newcomb's Problem by saying: "Let us not have, or let us not rely on, any intuitions about what is rational in goofball cases so unlike the decision problems of real life."
  2. But Prisoners' Dilemmas are deplorably common in real life. They are the most down-to-earth versions of Newcomb's Problem now available.


COMMENT:



"Lewis (David) - Causal Decision Theory"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 7: Dependence and Decision, Chapter 27

COMMENT: Also in "Gardenfors (Peter) & Sahlin (Nils-Eric), Eds. - Decision, Probability and Utility - Selected Readings"



"Lewis (David) - Utilitarianism and Truthfulness"

Source: Lewis - Philosophical Papers Volume II, Part 7: Dependence and Decision, Chapter 28



Text Colour Conventions (see disclaimer)
  1. Blue: Text by me; © Theo Todman, 2019
  2. Mauve: Text by correspondent(s) or other author(s); © the author(s)



© Theo Todman, June 2007 - Dec 2019. Please address any comments on this page to theo@theotodman.com. File output:
Website Maintenance Dashboard
Return to Top of this Page Return to Theo Todman's Philosophy Page Return to Theo Todman's Home Page