Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death?
Gasser (Georg), Ed.
This Page provides (where held) the Abstract of the above Book and those of all the Papers contained in it.
Text Colour-ConventionsBooks / Papers Citing this BookNotes Citing this Book

BOOK ABSTRACT:

Borrowed from Leeds University Library (via Billericay Library using the British Library Interlending scheme), and selectively copied.

Foreword (Full Text)

… By Ted Peters
  1. Perhaps the most profound and terrifying of existential questions is this one: what will happen to me when I die? Oblivion? Non-being? The forgetting of all that has been and the loss of all expectation of what will come? Or, might there be some truth to one or another religious claim? Immortal soul? Astral body? Reincarnation? Resurrection into God's new creation?
  2. How can we be sure? We cannot. What we can do is speculate. As we speculate we will try to draw mental pictures or construct conceptual models of what life beyond death might look like. As these mental pictures or conceptual models take shape, we can evaluate them. Do they make sense? Are they coherent? Are some better than others? Is it rational to believe that beyond death lies a hope that can enlist our devotion and inspire confidence in us?
  3. Demonstrating the rationality of belief in life beyond death is the task of the philosopher. Plato thought he could persuade us that the endurance of an immortal soul is something reasonable to believe in. Plato's dualism of body and soul is no longer persuasive, however. In our post-Enlightenment era we emphasize that human personhood is embodied personhood. Where might this lead us?
  4. The non-dualist alternative explored in the pages that follow is resurrection of the body. Is it rational for us to hope for a future resurrection in bodily form? If so, what will it look like? If death means the destruction of the body, what will be raised? A reassembling of the elements of our pre-mortem body? A brand new and perfected post-mortem body? Will it be "me" who is raised or will it be a duplicate of me? To think rationally here does not mean we can prove that resurrection will occur; but it does require that our mental picture or conceptual model demonstrate coherence.
  5. For us Christians who by faith rely upon God's promise that our future will include resurrection from the dead and life everlasting in God's kingdom, we need to understand it. We need to ask the theologians to help us understand just what resurrection of the body could mean. Are there grounds in divine revelation for reliance upon a divine promise? If so, how can we critically evaluate such a promise? Is it reasonable to speculate on the nature of our transfigured body as St. Paul describes it in 1 Corinthians 15:42-44: "So it is with the resurrection of the dead. What is sown is perishable, what is raised is imperishable. It is sown in dishonor, it is raised in glory. It is sown in weakness, it is raised in power. It is sown a physical body, it is raised a spiritual body." It appears that we can expect qualitative identity in the resurrection — that is, we can expect our existing bodies to undergo perfecting while we remain who we are. Yet, the metaphor of the seed being sown and later rising as something different raises the question of numerical identity: will the person in the resurrected body be "me" or a perfected duplicate? Just how can we imagine continuity of identity will be maintained?
  6. Such questions puzzle philosophers and theologians as they strive to construct rational models depicting what resurrection into an incorruptible spiritual body might look like. This task is a difficult one. Yet, the philosophers and theologians writing in the pages that follow take this task on with courage and creativity.

BOOK COMMENT:

Ashgate, Farnham, Surrey, 2010.



"Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Persons and the Metaphysics of Resurrection"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Author’s Abstract
    Theories of the human person differ greatly in their ability to underwrite a metaphysics of resurrection. This paper compares and contrasts a number of such views in light of the Christian doctrine of resurrection. In a Christian framework, resurrection requires that the same person who exists on earth also exists in an afterlife, that a post-mortem person be embodied, and that the existence of a post-mortem person is brought about by a miracle. According to my view of persons (the constitution view), a human person is constituted by – but not identical to – a human organism. A person has a first-person perspective essentially, and an organism has interrelated biological functions essentially. I shall argue for the superiority the constitution view as a metaphysical basis for resurrection.

Abstract1
    Theories of the human person differ greatly in their ability to underwrite a metaphysics of resurrection. Baker's paper compares and contrasts a number of such views in light of the Christian doctrine of resurrection. In a Christian framework, resurrection requires that the same person who exists on earth also exists in an afterlife, that a postmortem person be embodied, and that the existence of a postmortem person is brought about by a miracle. Baker advocates the Constitution View of a human person as a metaphysical basis for resurrection.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Persons and the Metaphysics of Resurrection")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser, a rather slavish but truncated copy of Baker’s Abstract of the original paper.



"Bruntrup (Godehard) - 3.5-Dimensionalism and Survival: A Process Ontological Approach"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Bruntrup develops a metaphysical framework which combines aspects of a four-dimensionalist space-time-ontology with a presentism. The key intuition is that the ontological base level of reality is thoroughly four-dimensional in the sense of a stage theory. This base level is a level of concrete event-like particulars. If ordered in a causal relation which establishes genidentity, this base level presents the constitution base for abstract time-invariant patterns. These patterns configure endurants, such as the human person. This metaphysical picture allows for a rather robust common-sense view of personal identity through time. It also is capable of accounting for post-mortem existence without having to make use of the notion of a Cartesian soul or the notion of a resurrected body identical to the earthly physical body.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Bruntrup (Godehard) - 3.5-Dimensionalism and Survival: A Process Ontological Approach")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Corcoran (Kevin) - Constitution, Resurrection, and Relationality"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Corcoran's paper points out that the Constitution View of the human person ought to be congenial to those stressing the relational character of personhood – a feature more salient in the continental tradition than in analytic philosophy. Corcoran addresses the issue of relationality head-on: first, he argues that relations figure crucially in the causal story of the emergence of a first-person perspective, because a social context seems required for the development of such a perspective. Second, he underlines that relationality is essential to a Christian understanding of eschatological transformation since we are created in the image of God, a God who exists in three persons engaged in mutually reciprocated, intimate, perichoretic relations of love.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Corcoran (Kevin) - Constitution, Resurrection, and Relationality")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Davis (Stephen T.) - Resurrection, Personal Identity, and the Will of God"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Davis places God in the centre of his paper: he argues that God is not only the creator but also the sustainer and preserver of all contingently existing things. In other words, personal identity through time is based not just on the person's immanent causal powers to persist but also on the fact that God sustains and upholds the person by recognizing and calling her. The will of God is, so to say, the "further fact" needed to resolve the troubling cases of personal identity-indeterminacy. Davis elaborates his approach by ruling out various possible misunderstandings of the notion of God as sustainer and preserver of all contingently existing things.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Davis (Stephen T.) - Resurrection, Personal Identity, and the Will of God")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: Bibliography"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Full Text
  • Abbott, Walter M.S.J., (ed.), The Documents of Vatican II (Louisville, KY: America Press, 1966).
  • Aristotle, De Anima, ed. W.D. Ross (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952).
    … see "Aristotle, Lawson-Tancred (Hugh) - De Anima (On the Soul)".
  • Athenagoras, De Resurrectione Mortuorum, ed. Miroslav Marcovich, Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae 53 (Leiden, Boston, and Koln: Brill, 2000).
    … see "Justin Martyr & Athenagoras - The Writings of Justin Martyr & Athenagoras".
  • Augustine,
    1. De Civitate Dei, ed. B. Dombert and A. Kalb (2 vols, Leipzig: Teubner 1863).
    2. The City of God (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1958).
      … see "Augustine, Healey (John), Barker (Barker) - The City of God".
    3. The Enchiridion on Faith, Hope, and Love (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1961).
  • Baker, Lynne Rudder,
    1. "Need a Christian Be a Mind/Body Dualist?", Faith and Philosophy, 12 (1995): 489-504.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Reply to Zimmerman’s "Christians Should Affirm Mind-Body Dualism"".
    2. "Why Constitution is not Identity", The Journal of Philosophy, 94 (1997): 599-622.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Why Constitution is Not Identity".
    3. "Unity without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution", in Peter A. French and Howard K. Wettstein (eds), New Directions in Philosophy, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Unity without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution".
    4. Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View".
    5. "Material Persons and the Doctrine of Resurrection", Faith and Philosophy, 18 (2001): 151-67.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Material Persons and the Doctrine of Resurrection".
    6. ”When Does a Person Begin?", Social Philosophy and Policy, 22 (2005): 25-48.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - When Does a Person Begin?".
    7. The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - The Metaphysics of Everyday Life: An Essay in Practical Realism".
    8. "Persons and the Metaphysics of Resurrection", Religious Studies, 43 (2007): 333-48.
      … see "Baker (Lynne Rudder) - Persons and the Metaphysics of Resurrection".
  • Baltimore, Joseph A., "Got to Have Soul", Religious Studies, 42 (2005): 417-30.
    … see "Baltimore (Joseph A.) - Got to Have Soul"
  • Barbour, Ian G., Religion in an Age of Science (Gifford Lectures: 1989-1990) (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1990).
    … see "Barbour (Ian) - Religion in an Age of Science".
  • Barrow, John D. and Tipler, Frank J., The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986).
    … see "Barrow (John) & Tipler (Frank) - The Anthropic Cosmological Principle".
  • Karl Barth, Karl, The Epistle to the Romans, trans. Edwyn C. Hoskyns, 6th edn (London: Oxford University Press, 1933).
  • Richard Bauckham, Richard and Hart, Trevor, Hope Against Hope: Christian Eschatology at the Turn of the Millennium (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 1999).
  • Brown, Christopher M., Aquinas and the Ship of Theseus. Solving Puzzles about Material Objects (London and New York: Continuum, 2005).
  • Bowne, Borden, Metaphysics: A Study in First Principles (New York: Harper. 1882).
  • Bruntrup, Godehard,
    1. "Is Psycho-Physical Emergentism Committed to Dualism? The Causal Efficacy of Emergent Mental Properties", Erkenntnis, 6 (1998 w: 1-19.
    2. Das Leib-Seele Problem (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 2008).
    3. "Soul, Body and Survival. The Renaissance of Christian Materialism”, Revista Portugesa de Filosofia, 65 Suppl. (2009): 317-35.
    4. "Natural Individuals and Intrinsic Properties", in Ludger Honnefelder, Edmund Runggaldier, and Benedikt Schick (eds), Unity and Time as Problem in Metaphysics (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2009), 237-52.
  • Bynum, Caroline Walker, The Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, 200-1336 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995).
    … see "Bynum (Caroline) - Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, 200 - 1336".
  • Caston, Victor, "Aristotle on Consciousness", Mind, 111 (2002): 751-815.
  • Cobb, John B. Jr. and Griffin, David Ray, Process Theology: An Introductory Exposition (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1976).
  • Corcoran, Kevin,
    1. "Persons and Bodies", Faith and Philosophy, 15 (1998): 324-40.
    2. (ed.), Soul, Body and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2001).
      … see "Corcoran (Kevin), Ed. - Soul, Body and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons".
    3. "Physical Persons and Postmortem Survival without Temporal Gaps". Kevin Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2001), 201-17.
      … see "Corcoran (Kevin) - Physical Persons and Postmortem Survival Without Temporal Gaps".
    4. ”The Constitution View of Persons", in Joel B. Green and Stuart L. Palmer (eds), In Search of the Soul. Four Views of the Mind-Body Problem (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2005), 153-76.
    5. "I'm not a Soul, Man: A Response to Baltimore", Religious Studies. (2005): 431-7.
      … see "Corcoran (Kevin) - I'm No Soul, Man: a Response to Baltimore".
    6. Rethinking Human Nature: A Christian Materialist Alternative to the Soul (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 2006).
    7. "Constitution, Resurrection, and Relationality", in Georg Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2010), 191-205.
      … see "Corcoran (Kevin) - Constitution, Resurrection, and Relationality".
  • Daley, Brian E., "A Hope for Worms", in Ted Peters, Robert J. Russell and Michael Welker (eds), Resurrection. Theological and Scientific Assessments (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2002), 136-64.
  • Darrow, Clarence, The Myth of the Soul (Girard, KS: Haldeman-Julius, 1929.
  • Davis, Stephen T.,
    1. Risen Indeed: Making Sense of the Resurrection (Grand Rapier.. MI: Eerdmans, 1993).
    2. "Physicalism and Resurrection", in Kevin Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2001), 229-48.
      … see "Davis (Stephen T.) - Physicalism and Resurrection".
    3. ”The Counterattack of the Resurrection Sceptics. A Review Article", Philosophia Christi, 8 (2005): 39-63.
  • Dawson, Robert Dale, The Resurrection in Karl Barth (Aldershot: Asghate, 2007).
  • Descartes, Rene,
    1. Meditations on First Philosophy, trans. Donald A. Cress (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979).
      … see "Descartes (Rene), Cottingham (John) - Meditations on First Philosophy - With Selections from the Objections and Replies"
    2. "Objections to Descartes Meditationes with Descartes' Replies", in Oeuvres de Descartes, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery (12 vols, Paris: J. Vrin, 1897-1913).
  • Dryer, Douglas P., Kant 's Solution for Verification in Metaphysics (Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1966).
  • Freeman Dyson, Freeman,
    1. "Time Without End: Physics and Biology in an Open Universe", Reviews of Modern Physics, 51 (1979): 447-60.
    2. Infinite in All Directions (New York: Harper & Row, 1988).
  • Eckl, Hermann Josef, "Seele", in Albert Franz, Wolfgang Baum, and Karsten Kreutzer (eds), Lexikon philosophischer Grundbegriffe der Theologie (Darmstadt: WBG 2003), 364-7.
  • Edwards, Denis,
    1. Jesus the Wisdom of God: An Ecological Theology (Homebush, Australia: St Pauls, 1995).
    2. The God of Evolution: A Trinitarian Theology (New, York: Paulist Press, 1999).
    3. "Every Sparrow That Falls to the Ground: The Cost of Evolution and the Christ-Event", Ecotheology, 11/1 (2006): 103-23.
  • Edwards, Jonathan, The Great Christian Doctrine of Original Sin Defended (1758), in The Works of Jonathan Edwards (Edinburgh: Banner of Truth, 1992).
  • Evans, Gareth, The Varieties of Reference (New York: Oxford University Press,
    1982).
    … see "Evans (Gareth), McDowell (John), Ed. - The Varieties of Reference"
  • Evans, Stephen, "Separable Souls: Dualism, Selfhood, and the Possibility of Life after Death", Christian Scholars Review, 34/3 (2005): 327-40.
  • Feldman, Fred,
    1. Confrontations with the Reaper (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992).
      … see "Feldman (Fred) - Confrontations with the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of the Nature and Value of Death"
    2. "The termination thesis", in Peter A. French and Howard K. Wettstein (eds), Life and Death: Metaphysics and Ethics, Midwest Studies in Philosophy 24 (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2000), 98-115.
      … see "Feldman (Fred) - The Termination Thesis"
  • Fiddes, Paul S., The Promised End. Eschatology in Theology and Literature (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000).
  • Flores, Tom, "The Perichoretic Negation of Sacred Violence: Foundational Possibilities for Reinventing Culture", Web Link (http://www.religion.emory.edu/affiliate/COVR/FloresWord.html) Defunct
  • Forrest, Peter, "The Tree of Life: Agency and Immortality in a Metaphysics Inspired by Quantum Theory", in Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman (eds), Persons: Human and Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
    … see "Forrest (Peter) - The Tree of Life: Agency and Immortality in a Metaphysics Inspired by Quantum Theory"
  • Forster, Eckart,
    1. Kant 's Final Synthesis. An Essay on Kant's Opus Postumum (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).
    2. The Twenty-Five Years of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2010).
  • Frankfurt, Harry, "The Logic of Omnipotence", Philosophical Review, 73/2 (1964): 262-3.
    … see "Frankfurt (Harry) - The Logic of Omnipotence"
  • Frede, Michael, "Aristotle's Notion of Potentiality in Metaphysics Theta", in Theodore Scaltas, David Charles, and Mary L. Gill (eds), Unity, Identity and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1994), 173-93.
    … See Michael Frede
  • Frege, Gottlob, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung uber den Begriff der Zahl (Breslau: Wilhelm Koebner, 1884).
    … see "Frege (Gottlob), Austin (J.L.) - The Foundations of Arithmetic"
  • Georg Gasser, Georg, "Lebewesen and Artefakte. Ontologische Unterscheidungen", Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 115 (2008): 125-47.
  • Goetz, Stewart, "Modal Dualism: A Critique", in Kevin Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2001), 89-104.
    … see "Goetz (Stewart) - Modal Dualism: A Critique"
  • Gould, Stephen Jay, Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life (New York: Ballantine Books, 2002).
    … see "Gould (Stephen Jay) - Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life"
  • Greshake, Gisbert,
    1. Auferstehung der Toten (Essen: Ludgerus, 1969).
    2. "Die Leib-Seele-Problematik and die Vollendung der Welt", in Gisbert Greshake and Gerhard Lohfink (eds), Naherwartung-Auferstehung-Unsterblichkeit: Untersuchungen zur christlichen Eschatologie, 4th edn (Freiburg i.B.: Herder, 1982), 156-84.
    3. … and Lohfink, Gerhard, Naherwartung, Auferstehung, Unsterblichkeit: Untersuchungen zur christlichen Eschatologie, 5 edn, Quaestiones Disputatae 71 (Freiburg: Herder, 1986).
    4. … and Kremer, Jacob, Resurrectio mortuorum: zum theologischen Verstandnis der leiblichen Auferstehung (Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. 1986).
  • Haag, Johannes, Erfahrung and Gegenstand. Das Verhaltnis von Sinnlichkeit and Verstand (Frankfurt a.M.: Klostermann, 2007).
  • Hale, Bob and Wright, Crispin, "The Meta-Ontology of Abstraction", in David Chalmers et al. (eds), Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology (Oxford: Clarendon 2009), 178-212.
    … see "Hale (Bob) & Wright (Crispin) - The Metaontology of Abstraction"
  • Harnack, Adolph, History of Dogma, trans. Neil Buchanan (7 vols, New York: Dover, 1961).
  • William Hasker, William, The Emergent Self (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999).
  • Haught, John F.,
    1. The Promise of Nature: Ecology and Cosmic Purpose (New York: Paulist Press, 1993).
    2. God After Darwin: A Theology of Evolution (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2000).
  • Herbert, Robert T., Paradox and Identity in Theology (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979).
  • Hershenov, David,
    1. "Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the materialist conception of resurrection", Religious Studies, 38 (2002): 451-69.
      … see "Hershenov (David) - Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection"
    2. "The Metaphysical Problem of Intermittent Existence and the Possibility of Resurrection", Faith and Philosophy, 20 (2003): 24-36.
    3. … and Koch-Hershenov, Rose J., "Personal Identity and Purgatory", Religious Studies, 42 (2006): 439-51.
      … see "Hershenov (David) & Koch-Hershenov (Rose J.) - Personal identity and Purgatory"
  • Hudson, Hud,
    1. A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001).
      … see "Hudson (Hud) - A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person"
    2. The Metaphysics of Hyperspace (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).
    3. "I am Not an Animal!", in Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman (eds), Persons: Human and Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 216-34.
      … see "Hudson (Hud) - I am Not an Animal!"
    4. "Precis of The Metaphysics of Hyperspace", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76/2 (2008): 422-6.
    5. "Reply to Parsons, Reply to Heller, and Reply to Rea", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76/2 (2008): 452-70.
    6. "Omnipresence", in Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
  • Huggett, Nick, "Identity, Quantum Mechanics and Common Sense", The Monist, 80 (1997): 118-30.
  • Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. P.H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon, 1978).
    … see "Hume (David), Mossner (Ernest) - A Treatise of Human Nature"
  • Edmund Husserl, Edmund,
    1. Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften and die transzendentale Phanomenologie, Part II (Hamburg: Meiner, 1992).
    2. Cartesianische Meditationen: Eine Einleitung in die Phanomenologie, 3rd edn (Hamburg: Meiner-Verlag, 1995).
  • Johnston, Mark, "Human Beings", Journal of Philosophy, 84 (1987): 59-83.
    … see "Johnston (Mark) - Human Beings"
  • Jolivet, Jean, "Elements pour une etude des rapports entre la grammaire et l'ontologie au moyen age", in Jan Beckmann and Ludger Honnefelder (eds), Sprache and Erkenntnis im Mittelalter, Miscellanea MediaevaIia 13/1 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1981), 135-64.
  • Immanuel Kant, Immanuel, Kants Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Deutschen Akademie der Wissenschaften (29 vols, Berlin: De Gruyter, 1902-1983).
  • Kirwan, Michael, Discovering Girard (London: Darton, Longman & Todd, 2004).
  • Kortner, Ulrich H.J., The End of the World: A Theological Interpretation, trans. Douglas W. Stott (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 1995).
  • Kranz, Walter, Die griechische Philosophie, reprint of the 5th edn (Munchen: dtv, 1971).
  • LaCugna, Catherine, God For Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (San Francisco: Harper Collins, 1991).
  • Leftow, Brian, "Souls Dipped in Dust", in Kevin Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival. Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), 120-38.
    … see "Leftow (Brian) - Souls Dipped in Dust"
  • Levin, Kurt, Der Begriffder Genese in Physik, Biologie und Entwicklungsgeschichte. Eine Untersuchung zur vergleichenden Wissenschaftslehre (Berlin: Springer, 1922).
  • Lewis, David,
    1. "Survival and Identity", in A. Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons (Berkeley, CA: 1976), reprinted in David Lewis, Philosophical Papers (2 vols, New York: Oxford University Press, 1983), vol. 1, 55-72.
      … see "Lewis (David) - Survival and Identity"
    2. On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).
      … see "Lewis (David) - On the Plurality of Worlds"
  • Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Alexander C. Fraser (2 vols, New York: Dover, 1959).
    … see "Locke (John), Nidditch (Peter) - An Essay Concerning Human Understanding"
  • Michael Loux, Michael, Metaphysics. A Contemporary Introduction, 3rd edn (New York: Routledge, 2006).
  • Lowe, Ernest Jonathan,
    1. The Possibility of Metaphysics. Substance, Identity, and Time (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).
      … see "Lowe (E.J.) - The Possibility of Metaphysics: Substance, Identity and Time"
    2. A Survey of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
      … see "Lowe (E.J.) - A Survey of Metaphysics"
  • Luke, Ulrich, "Auferstehung am tungsten Tag als Auferstehung im Tod", Stimmen der Zeit, 216 (1998): 45-54.
  • MacKay, Donald M., "Brain Science and the Soul", in Richard L. Gregory (ed.). The Oxford Companion to the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987). 724-5.
    … see "Gregory (Richard), Ed. - Oxford Companion to the Mind",
    … and Donald MacKay
  • John Macquarrie, John, Principles of Christian Theology, 2nd edn (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1977).
  • Marschler, Thomas, "Perspektiven der Eschatologie bei Joseph Ratzinger", in Peter Hofmann (ed.), Joseph Ratzinger: Ein theologisches Profil (Paderborn: Schoningh, 2008), 161-91.
  • Mavrodes, George, "The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity". Nous, 11(1977): 27-39.
    … see "Mavrodes (George I.) - The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity"
  • McCord Adams, Marilyn, "The Resurrection of the Body according to Three Medieval Aristotelians: Thomas Aquinas, John Duns Scotus, William Ockham", Philosophical Topics, 20 (1993): 1-33.
    … See Marilyn McCord Adams
  • Kris McDaniel, Kris, "Extended Simples", Philosophical Studies, 133 (2007): 13141.
  • McFayden, Alistair I., The Call to Personhood. A Christian Theory of the Individual in Social Relationships (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
  • Mead, George Herbert, Mind, Self and Society (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1934).
  • Meixner, Uwe,
    1. The Two Sides of Being: A Reassessment of Psycho-Physical Dualism (Paderborn: Mentis, 2004).,
    2. "The Indispensability of the Soul", in Bruno Niederbacher and Edmund Runggaldier (eds), Die menschliche Seele: Brauchen wir den Dualismus? (Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag, 2006), 19-40.
  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Phenomenology of Perception (London and New York: Routledge, 1962), 77-232.
    … See Maurice Merleau-Ponty for Part 1.
  • Merricks, Trenton,
    1. "There Are No Criteria of Identity Over Time", Nous, 32 (1998): 106-24.
      … see "Merricks (Trenton) - There Are No Criteria For Identity Over Time"
    2. "The Resurrection of the Body and the Life Everlasting", in Michael Murray (ed.), Reason for the Hope Within (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 1999), 261-86.
    3. "How to Live Forever without Saving Your Soul: Physicalism and immortality", in Kevin Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001).
      … see "Merricks (Trenton) - How to Live Forever Without Saving Your Soul: Physicalism and Immortality"
    4. Objects and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003).
      … see "Merricks (Trenton) - Objects and Persons"
    5. “The Resurrection of the Body", in Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 476-90.
  • Meyer, Hans, Thomas von Aquin (Bonn: Peter Hanstein, 1938).
  • Moltmann, Jurgen,
    1. "God in Creation: A New Theology of Creation and the Spirit of God" (The Gifford Lectures 1984-1985) (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1985).
    2. The Way of Jesus Christ: Christology in Messianic Dimensions, trans. Margaret Kohl (London: SCM, 1990).
    3. The Coming of God: Christian Eschatology, trans. Margaret Kohl, 1st Fortress Press edn (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1996).
    4. In the End — The Beginning, trans. Margaret Kohl (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2004).
  • Muller, Tobias, Gott, Welt, Kreativitat. Eine Analyse der Philosophie A.N. Whiteheads (Paderborn: Schoningh, 2009).
  • Murray, Michael, "Coercion and the Hiddenness of God", American Philosophical Quarterly, 30 (1993): 27-38.
  • Nachtwei, Gerhard, Dialogische Unsterblichkeit. Eine Untersuchung zu Joseph Ratzingers Eschatologie and Theologie, Erfurter Theologische Studien 54 (Leipzig: St. Benno, 1986).
  • Niewiadomski, Jozef, "Denial of the Apocalypse versus Fascination with the Final Days: Current Theological Discussion of Apocalyptic Thinking in the Perspective of Mimetic Theory", in Robert G. Hamerton-Kelly (ed.), Politics & Apocalypse, Studies in Violence, Mimesis, and Culture (East Lansing, MI: Michigan State University Press, 2007), 51-67.
  • Noonan, Harold, Personal Identity (London and New York: Routledge, 1989).
    … see "Noonan (Harold) - Personal Identity"
  • Olson, Eric T.,
    1. The Human Animal (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
      … see "Olson (Eric) - The Human Animal - Personal Identity Without Psychology"
    2. What are we? A Study in Personal Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University
      Press, 2007).
      … see "Olson (Eric) - What are We?"
    3. "Immanent Causation and Life After Death", in Georg Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2010), 51-66.
      … see "Olson (Eric) - Immanent Causation and Life After Death"
  • Palmer, Stuart L., "Christian Life and Theories of Human Nature", in Joel B. Green and Stuart L. Palmer (eds), In Search of the Soul. Four News of the Mind-Body Problem (Downers Grove: Intervarsity Press, 2005), 189-215.
  • Pannenberg, Wolfhart,
    1. Theology and the Kingdom of God, ed. Richard John Neuhaus (Philadelphia: The Westminster Press, 1969).
    2. "Theological Questions to Scientists", in Arthur R. Peacocke (ed.), The Sciences and Theology in the Twentieth Century (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981).
    3. Theologie and Philosophie (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck, 1996).
    4. Systematic Theology, trans. Geoffrey W. Bromiley (3 vols, Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 1998).
  • Parfit, Derek, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986).
    … see "Parfit (Derek) - Reasons and Persons"
  • Pasnau, Robert, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002).
  • Arthur Peacocke, Arthur,
    1. Theology for a Scientific Age: Being and Becoming — Natural, Divine and Human, enlarged edn (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1993).
    2. "The Cost of New Life", in John Polkinghorne (ed.), The Work of Love: Creation as Kenosis (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2001).
  • Perry, John, "The importance of being identical", in Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. 1976).
    … see "Perry (John) - The Importance of Being Identical"
  • Peters, Ted,
    1. God — the World's Future: Systematic Theology for a Postmodern Era (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 1992).
    2. God as Trinity: Relationality and Temporality in the Divine Life (Louisville. KY: Westminster/John Knox Press, 1993).
    3. "Where Are We Going? Eschatology", in William C. Placher (ed.), Essentials of Christian Theology (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 2003), 34765.
    4. Anticipating Omega: Science, Faith, and Our Ultimate Future (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2006).
  • John Polkinghorne, John,
    1. Reason and Reality: The Relationship Between Science and Theology (Valley Forge, PA: Trinity Press International, 1991).
      … see "Polkinghorne (John) - Reason and Reality: The relationship between science and theology"
    2. The Faith of a Physicist: Reflections of a Bottom-Up Thinker (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1996).
    3. Science and Theology: An Introduction (London and Minneapolis: SPCK and Fortress, 1998).
    4. "Eschatology: Some Questions and Some Insights from Science", in John Polkinghorne and Michael Welker (eds), The End of the World and the Ends of God: Science and Theology on Eschatology (Harrisburg: Trinity Press International, 2000), 29-41.
    5. The God of Hope and the End of the World (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002).
  • Pope Benedict XVI., "Litterae Encyclicae Spe salvi", Acta Apostolicae Sedis, 99 (2007): 985-1027.
  • Price, Henry H., "Survival and the Idea of Another World", Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, 50 (1953): 1-15.
    … see "Price (H.H.) - Survival and the Idea of "Another World""
  • Puntel, Lorenz B., Structure and Being (University Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 2008).
  • Quine, Willard V.O., Word and Object (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1960).
    … see "Quine (W.V.) - Word & Object"
  • Karl Rahner, Karl,
    1. Zur Theologie des Todes, Quaestiones Disputatae 2 (Freiburg: Herder, 1958).
    2. ”The Theological Concept of Concupiscentia", Theological Investigations 1: God, Christ, Mary, and Grace (23 vols, Baltimore, MD: Helicon, 1961), 347-82.
    3. ”The Eternal Significance of the Humanity of Jesus for Our Relationship with God", Theological Investigations 3: The Theology of Spiritual Life (23 vols, Baltimore, MD: Helicon Press, 1967), 35-46.
    4. ”The Theology of the Symbol", Theological Investigations 4: More Recent Writings (23 vols, Baltimore, MD: Helicon Press, 1966), 221-52.
    5. "Theology of Freedom", Theological Investigations 6: Concerning Vatican Council II (23 vols, Baltimore, MD: Helicon Press, 1969), 178-96.
    6. The Priesthood, trans. Edward Quinn (New York, 1973).
  • Ratzinger, Joseph,
    1. "Auferstehung des Fleisches": "I. Lehre der Kirche" and "VI. Dogmengeschichte", Lexikon fur Theologie and Kirche, 2nd edn (2 vols, Freiburg, Basel, and Wien: Herder 1957), vol. 1, cols 1042 and 1048-52.
    2. Die sakramentale Begrundung christlicher Existenz (Meitingen: Kyrios, 1966).
    3. "Auferstehung des Fleisches", Sacramentum Mundi, 1 (1967): cols 397402.
    4. Eschatologie: Tod and ewiges Leben, Kleine Katholische Dogmatik 9, 2nd edn (Regensburg: Pustet, 1978).
    5. "Zwischen Tod and Auferstehung", Theologisches Jahrbuch, (1985): 27490.
    6. Introduction to Christianity (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2004).
    7. Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life (Washington, D.C: CUA Press, 2007).
  • Rea, Michael C., "Temporal Parts Unmotivated", The Philosophical Review, 107 (1998): 225-60.
    … see "Rea (Michael) - Temporal Parts Unmotivated"
  • Redhead, Michael and Teller, Paul, "Particle Labels & the Theory of Indistinguishable Particles in Quantum Mechanics", British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 43 (1992): 201-18.
    … maybe compare "French (Steven) & Redhead (Michael) - Quantum Physics and the Identity of Indiscernibles"
  • Reichenbach, Bruce, Is Man the Phoenix? A Study of Immortality (Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1983).
    … See Bruce Reichenbach
  • Remenyi, Matthias, "Mit Stimme, Antlitz and Gestalt: Uberlegungen zur personalen Eschatologie", Theologie and Glaube, 96/1 (2006): 73-86.
  • Rescher, Nicholas, Process Metaphysics. An Introduction to Process Philosophy (New York: Suny Press, 1996).
  • Ricceur, Paul, Oneself as Another (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992).
  • Rosenberg, Gregg, A Place for Consciousness. Probing the Deep Structure of the Natural World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
  • Runggaldier, Edmund, "The Aristotelian Alternative to Functionalism and Dualism", in Bruno Niederbacher and Edmund Runggaldier (eds), Die menschliche Seele: Brauchen wir den Dualismus? (Heusenstamm: Ontos. 2006), 221-48.
  • Russell, Bertrand,
    1. "Free Man's Worship", Mysticism and Logic, and Other Essays (London: Allen & Unwin, 1963).
      … see "Russell (Bertrand) - A Free Man's Worship"
    2. The Analysis of Matter (London: Routledge, 1992).
  • Russell, Robert John,
    1. "Did God Create Our Universe? Theological Reflections on the Big Bang, Inflation and Quantum Cosmologies", Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 950: Cosmic Questions (2001): 108-27.
    2. "The Relevance of Tillich for the Theology and Science Dialogue", Zygon:. 36/2 (2001): 269-308.
    3. "Bodily Resurrection, Eschatology and Scientific Cosmology: The Mutate Interaction of Christian Theology and Science", in Ted Peters, Robert John Russell, and Michael Welker (eds), Resurrection: Theological and Scientific Assessments (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2002), 3-30.
    4. "Eschatology and Physical Cosmology: A Preliminary Reflection", in George F.R. Ellis (ed.), The Far Future: Eschatology from a Cosmic Perspective (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press, 2002), 266-315.
    5. "Sin, Salvation, and Scientific Cosmology: Is Christian Eschatology Credible Today?" in Duncan Reid and Mark Worthing (eds), Sin and Salvation (Hindmarsh: ATF Press, 2003), 130-54.
    6. Cosmology from Alpha to Omega: The Creative Mutual Interaction Theology and Science (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 2008).
    7. "Cosmology and Eschatology", in Jerry Walls (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Eschatology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008).
    8. Time in Eternity: Pannenberg, Physics and Eschatology in Creative Mutual Interaction (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2011).
  • Ryle, Gilbert, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1949).
    … see "Ryle (Gilbert) - The Concept of Mind"
  • Saucedo, Raul, "Parthood and Location", in Dean Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 4 [forthcoming].
  • Saunders, Simon, "Are Quantum Particles Objects?", Analysis, 66 (2006): 52-63.
    … see "Saunders (Simon) - Are Quantum Particles Objects?"
  • Schartl, Thomas,
    1. "Was heisst 'Auferstehung des Leibes'?" in Franz Gruber et al (eds), Homo animal materiale. Die materielle Bestimmtheit des Menschen (Wien: Wagner, 2008), 105-49.
    2. "Where Metaphysics Needs Phenomenology", in Georg Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2010), 103-25.
      … see "Schartl (Thomas) - Bodily Resurrection: When Metaphysics Needs Phenomenology"
  • Schneider, Theodor, Handbuch der Dogmatik (2 vols, Dusseldorf: Patmos, 1992).
  • Schwager, Raymund S.J.,
    1. "Die heutige Theologie and das leere Grab Jesu", Zeitschrift fur katholische Theologie, 115 (1993): 435-50.
    2. Jesus in the Drama of Salvation: Toward a Biblical Doctrine of Redemption, trans. James G. Williams and Paul Haddon (New York: The Crossroad, 1999).
  • Schwarz, Hans, Eschatology (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2000).
  • Seager, William, "Rosenberg, Reducibility, and Consciousness", Psyche, 12 (2006): 1-15.
  • Sellars, Wilfrid,
    1. "Some Remarks on Kant's Theory of Experience", Journal of Philosophy, 64 (1967): 633-47.
    2. "Kant's Transcendental Idealism", Collections of Philosophy, 6 (1976): 165-81 (Web Link)
      … see "Sellars (Wilfrid) - Kant's Transcendental Idealism"
  • Shivola, Juha, "The Problem of Consciousness in Aristotle's Philosophy", in S. Heinamaa, V. Lahteenmaki, and P. Remes (eds), Consciousness: From Perception to Reflection in the History of Philosophy (Dordrecht: Springer, 2007), 49-66.
  • Shoemaker, Sydney,
    1. "Personal identity: A materialist's account", in Sydney Shoemaker and Richard Swinburne (eds), Personal Identity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984).
      … see "Shoemaker (Sydney) - Personal Identity: a Materialist Account"
    2. Physical Realization (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).
      … see "Shoemaker (Sydney) - Physical Realization"
  • Shults, LeRon,
    1. "The Philosophical Turn to Relationality", in Dana Wright (ed.), Redemptive Transformation in Practical Theology (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2002), 325-46.
    2. Reforming Theological Anthropology. After the Philosophical Turn to Relationality (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2002).
  • Ronald J Sider, Theodore,
    1. "Review of Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies", The Journal of Philosophy, 99 (2001): 45-8.
    2. Four-Dimensionalism. An Ontology of Persistence and Time (Oxford: Clarendon, 2003).
      … see "Sider (Ted) - Four-dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time"
    3. "Parthood", Philosophical Review, 116 (2007): 51-91.
  • Simons, Peter,
    1. "The Thread of Persistence", in Christian Kanzian (ed.), Persistence (Heusenstamm: Ontos, 2008), 165-84.
    2. … and Melia, Joseph, "Continuants and Occurrents", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 74 (2000): 59-92.
  • Simpson, Peter, "Aristotle's Idea of the Self', The Journal of Value Inquiry, 35 (2001): 309-24.
    … See Peter Simons
  • David Skrbina, David, Panpsychism in the West (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005).
  • Strawson, Galen, Selves: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
    … See Galen Strawson
  • Strawson, Peter F., Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (Oxford: Routledge, 1959).
    … see "Strawson (Peter) - Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics"
  • Eleonore Stump, Eleonore,
    1. Aquinas (London: Routledge, 2003).
    2. "Resurrection, Reassembly, and Reconstitution: Aquinas on the Soul", in Bruno Niederbacher and Edmund Runggaldier (eds), Die menschliche Seele: Brauchen wir den Dualismus? (Heusenstamm: Ontos, 2006), 153-74.
  • Suchocki, Marjorie H., The End of Evil: Process Eschatology in Historical Context (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988).
  • Swinburne, Richard, The Evolution of the Soul, revised edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
    … see "Swinburne (Richard) - The Evolution of the Soul"
  • Tanner, Kathryn, "Eschatology without a Future?", in John Polkinghorne and Michael Welker (eds), The End of the World and the Ends of God (Harrisburg: Trinity Press International, 2000).
  • Tapp, Christian, "Joseph Ratzinger on Resurrection Identity", in Georg Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection. How Do We Survive Our Death? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2010), 207-24.
    … See "Tapp (Christian) - Joseph Ratzinger on Resurrection Identity"
  • Tertullian, De Carne Christi, text ed. with an introduction, translation and commentary by Ernest Evans (London: SPCK, 1956).
  • Thielicke, Helmut, Being Human... Becoming Human (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1984).
  • Thomas DominicansAquinas,
    1. Corpus Thomisticum: S. Thomae De Aquino Opera Omnia: (Web Link).
    2. Commentarium super epistolam I ad Corinthios (Turin 1953).
    3. De ente et essentia, (Rome 1976).
    4. De mixtione elementorum, (Romae 1976).
    5. De spiritualibus creaturis, (Turin 1953).
    6. Expositio super librum Boethii, (Turin 1954).
    7. Quaestio disputata de anima, (Turin 1953).
    8. Scriptum super libros Sententiarum, (Parma 1856).
    9. Sententia libri de anima, (Turin 1959).
    10. Summa contra Gentiles, (Turin 1961).
    11. Summa Theologiae, (Rome 1888).
  • Tye, Michael, "In defense of the Words ‘Human Body’", Philosophical Studies, 38 (1980): 177-82.
    … see "Tye (Michael) - In Defense of the Words 'Human Body'"
  • van Inwagen, Peter,
    1. "The Possibility of Resurrection", International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 9 (1978): 114-21, reprinted in Paul Edwards (ed.), Immortality (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1997), 242-6.
      … see "Van Inwagen (Peter) - The Possibility of Resurrection"
    2. ”The Possibility of Resurrection", in Peter van Inwagen (ed.), The Possibility of Resurrection and Other Essays in Christian Apologetics (Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1998), 45-51.
    3. "Philosophers and the Words ‘Human Body’", in Peter van Inwagen (ed.), Time and Cause (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1980), 283-99.
      … see "Van Inwagen (Peter) - Philosophers and the Words 'Human Body'"
    4. "Four-Dimensional Objects", Nous, 24 (1990[a]): 245-55.
      … see "Van Inwagen (Peter) - Four-Dimensional Objects"
    5. Material Beings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1990[b]).
      … see "Van Inwagen (Peter) - Material Beings"
    6. "Dualism and Materialism: Athens and Jerusalem", Faith and Philosophy, 12 (1995): 475-88.
    7. "Resurrection", in Eduard Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (10 vols, London: Routledge, 1998), vol. 8, 294-6.
    8. "A Materialist Ontology of the Human Person", in Peter van Inwagen and Dean Zimmerman (eds), Persons: Human and Divine (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007): 199-215.
      … see "Van Inwagen (Peter) - A Materialist Ontology of the Human Person"
  • Wandinger, Nikolaus,
    1. "Der Begriff der 'Aeternitas' bei Thomas von Aquin", Zeitschrift fur katholische Theologie, 116 (1994): 301-20.
    2. Die Sundenlehre als Schlussel zum Menschen. Impulse K. Rahners and R. Schwagers zu einer Heuristik theologischer Anthropologie (Munster: LIT, 2003).
  • Weinberg, Steven, The First Three Minutes: A Modern View of the Origin of the Universe (New York: Basic Books, 1977).
    … See Steven Weinberg
  • Wheeler, David, "Toward a Process-Relational Christian Eschatology", Process Studies, 22 (1993): 227-37.
  • Alfred North Whitehead, Alfred N.,
    1. The Concept of Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1920).
    2. Process and Reality (New York: The Free Press, 1978).
  • Wiggins, David, Sameness and Substance (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980).
    … see "Wiggins (David) - Sameness and Substance", and
    … "Wiggins (David) - Sameness and Substance Renewed",
  • Wilkes, Kathleen V., Real People: Personal Identity without Thought Experiments (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).
    … see "Wilkes (Kathleen) - Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments"
  • Williams, Bernard, "Personal Identity and Individuation" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 76 (1956-1957): 229-52.
    … see "Williams (Bernard) - Personal Identity and Individuation"
  • Woltersdorff, Nicholas, "How Philosophical Theology Became Possible with the Analytic Tradition of Philosophy", in Oliver D. Crisp and Michael C. Rea (eds), Analytic Theology. New Essays in the Philosophy of Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 155-68.
  • Dean Zimmerman, Dean,
    1. "Immanent causation", Nous 31, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives 11: Mind, Causation, and World (1997): 433-71.
      … see "Zimmerman (Dean) - Immanent Causation"
    2. "Materialism and Survival", in Eleonore Stump and Michael Murray (eds), Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998), 379-86.
    3. "Criteria of Identity and the ‘Identity Mystics’", Erkenntnis, 48 (1998): 281-301.
      … see "Zimmerman (Dean) - Criteria of Identity and the 'Identity Mystics'"
    4. "The Compatibility of Materialism and Survival: The ‘Falling Elevator' Model", Faith and Philosophy, 16 (1999): 194-212.
    5. "Material People", in Michael Loux and Dean Zimmerman (eds), Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 491526.
      … see "Zimmerman (Dean) - Material People"
    6. "Should a Christian Be a Mind-Body Dualist?", in M. Peterson and R. Van Arragon (eds), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (Malden, MA: Basil Blackwell, 2004), 315-27.
      … see "Zimmerman (Dean) - Christians Should Affirm Mind-Body Dualism"
    7. "Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited", in Georg Gasser (ed.), Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2010), 33-50.
      … see "Zimmerman (Dean) - Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited"
    8. "From Property Dualism to Substance Dualism", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 85: 119-150.


COMMENT:



"Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: Introduction"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Full Text (some reformatting done, my own comments added as footnotes)
    If there is no resurrection of the dead, then not even Christ has been raised. And if Christ has not been raised, our preaching is useless and so is your faith1. (I Cor 15:13-14)

The Intellectual Background
  1. The last four decades or so testify to a remarkable development in the academic climate of analytic philosophy. Stephen T. Davis witnessed this development from his college time in the late sixties and seventies onward. He writes: "in those days, we students were scarcely allowed even to mention words like ‘God' or ‘theology', and claims like ‘God raised Jesus from the dead' were dismissed with disdain, scorn and knowing looks2." Nowadays, instead, many philosophers, believers and non-believers alike, explicitly dedicate their work to religious topics. Philosophy of religion has become a respectable discipline within analytic philosophy.
  2. Conjecture abounds for the reasons3 for this development. In a recent article4, Nicholas Wolterstorff identifies three major ones:
    • First, logical positivism, once dominant among analytic philosophers, was unable to articulate in a satisfactory way its key concept of empirical verifiability. This inability proved to be positivism's5 downfall. The regressing influence of positivism paved the way for a rising interest in metaphysics in general and an open attitude to philosophical research of religious topics in particular.
    • Second, this shift in analytic philosophy went hand in hand with a waning interest in the theme preoccupying classical modem philosophy: the limits of the thinkable and the assertible. Whereas philosophers in the tradition of Enlightment are concerned that our epistemological limitations might make it impossible to investigate certain kinds of topics in a meaningful way, analytic philosophers today no longer share this concern. They are thus more open to all sorts of inquiry, including metaphysics and philosophical reflection on theological doctrines.
    • Finally, according to Wolterstorff, the third important development within analytic philosophy was the flourishing of meta-epistemology, that is, explicit investigation of alternative6 models of knowledge. Classical foundationalism — the view, roughly, that a belief is justified only if it rests ultimately on a foundation of non-inferential knowledge — was seen no longer as the only respectable epistemological theory. This made room for epistemological positions that were friendly towards the view that one might rationally hold religious beliefs.
  3. These three developments eliminated important obstacles to a more intense analysis of religious beliefs. Analytic philosophy became less uniform and led to a multitude of examinations concerning a vast array of themes. No wonder, then, that Wolterstorff describes current philosophical discourse as pluralistic:
      For want of a better term, call the picture of the philosophical enterprise that I have just sketched, dialogic pluralism. Philosophy is now widely assumed, by analytic philosophers, to be a dialogical pluralist enterprise7.
    Such a pluralistic8 enterprise is reminiscent of the situation in late antiquity when Stoics, Christians, Sceptics, Neoplatonists, and Aristotelians all contributed to shaping intellectual discourse. There was no body of principles or insights that all agreed on. Instead, proponents of the various schools met publicly, discussed and argued with each other, and when an argument was proven to be poor, the school which put it forward tried to improve and to articulate it in more detail. Analytic philosophy nowadays is like that: philosophers being reductive naturalists, non-reductive naturalists, non-naturalists, theists, and so on form a pluralistic mix, each philosophical strand representing a legitimate and important participant in dialogue. Such a situation offers an intellectual openness which encourages experimentation.
  4. This volume testifies to this courage to experiment: though all9 authors are sympathetic toward the possibility of resurrection, their starting points and intellectual resources for justifying it range from materialist to dualist conceptions of the human person and involve classical theological approaches, recent analytic metaphysics, and various ideas from continental philosophy.

Specifying the Problem: Mind the Gap
  1. Belief in some form of post-mortem survival is not extravagant. Take, for instance, Platonic Dualism: According to this view, bodies die and decay whereas an immaterial soul continues to live. The idea is that the soul naturally survives biological death for it is the nature of a soul to be incorruptible. Furthermore, this view claims that the soul is the essence of a human person: you are your soul, not your body. Though such a belief might be at odds with a materialist understanding of reality, it does not appear incomprehensible from a metaphysical point of view. Once you have accepted that incorruptible souls exist which are the essences of human persons, it is not presumptuous to claim that human persons live forever due to soul's incorruptible nature, whereas human bodies disintegrate.
  2. Belief in bodily resurrection, on the contrary, seems to be another matter together. It seems at the very least an odd belief indeed. Even its proponents are aware of this. Tertullian, one of the first Christian theologians in the West, wrote famously that "the resurrection of Jesus Christ is certain — because it is impossible10".
  3. Of course, Tertullian wants to provoke his pagan contemporaries. Nevertheless, he expresses a view which most of his contemporaries (and probably the majority today) deemed to be true: the bodily resurrection of Jesus of Nazareth seems to be impossible, if taken literally. The problem of the resurrection of the body multiplies, for it concerns not only the unique person with human and divine nature, Jesus Christ. Christian faith claims also that all human persons who have ever lived on earth will be resurrected. Jesus Christ's resurrection is the anticipation11 of all people's resurrection. The early church affirmed this belief explicitly in the Nicene and the Apostles’ Creeds. As documents summarizing the most important beliefs of Christian faith, the creeds make clear that the doctrine of bodily resurrection is not an addendum to Christian faith but belongs at its very core. Karl Barth, one of the most influential theologians of the previous century, for instance, underlines that the doctrine of bodily resurrection is the basic axiom of Christian faith: It is the key to the whole. And Adolph Harnack, the eminent church historian from the turn of the twentieth century, says that "the resurrection of Jesus became the pledge of the resurrection of all believers, that is of their real personal resurrection. No one at the beginning thought of a mere immortality of the spirit12."
  4. Why, then, is it apparently so much more difficult to believe in the resurrection of the body than in the survival of a disembodied soul or spirit?
  5. People are inclined to think that the body I have this afternoon is the same body that I had a week ago and that I will have at the end of the week. The view that I have one single body during my entire lifetime does not imply, however, that my body cannot change. The body I have now is very different from the body I had even a few days ago. At a very small scale it changed in size, weight and physiological composition. The body is continuously changing but nevertheless remains the same body. A good reason supporting such a view is the distinction between numerical identity and qualitative identity: when a thing changes, it remains numerically the same but becomes different in its qualities. In the process of change new acquired bodily qualities connect to already existing ones. So the same body has different qualities at different times, but these changes do not result in the old body's ceasing to exist and a new one's being generated.
  6. Is the resurrection of the body an instance of qualitative change? In light of the aforementioned distinction it would not be particularly bold to claim that our earthly body metamorphoses13 into a new one by acquiring heavenly "incorruptible" properties and losing the earthly "corruptible" ones. There would just be one more — admittedly miraculous — process of change in the long chain of natural bodily changes.
  7. The reason, however, why this traditional metaphysical solution to the problem of change cannot be applied to the Christian doctrine of resurrection is that death14 is the definite end of a human being's existence on earth15. If human persons are bodily beings which die and thereby cease to exist, then their bodies decay, are eaten by animals or destroyed in the fire of a crematory. Thanks to common sense and science, it is safe to say that nothing remains of human bodies after a certain period of time. There is simply no physical entity left which could16 acquire new qualities.
  8. Nevertheless, the creeds hold that the very same human persons who lived on earth will rise and exist again in bodily form. That is, the doctrine of bodily resurrection seems to admit that there is a gap between the earthly bodily existence of human persons and their resurrection. This gap is the reason why it is so much more difficult to believe in bodily resurrection than in the survival of the soul: many see no possibility to bridge the gap which death rips open between pre- and post-mortem human existence. There is simply nothing left of our human bodily existence which could cross the gap so as to preserve numerical identity. God certainly has the power to create a new body which is a duplicate of the earthly one. Such a duplicate, however, would not be the same body which existed at a determinate time in the history of the cosmos. The earthly body and its heavenly duplicate would have different histories: the latter was never on earth, the former never in heaven. There is thus not one and the same entity with different qualities but two numerically different entities with different qualities. Even for an all-powerful being it seems impossible to bring back into existence an entity which utterly ceased to exist. Nor could God suspend the metaphysical principle that the same entity cannot come into existence twice17.
  9. If these thoughts are correct, then Tertullian's statement is not just provocative rhetoric but makes a crucial point: The Christian doctrine of bodily resurrection seems to require a metaphysical impossibility in order to be true. If there is no identity between the pre-mortem and the post-mortem body in the sense that this very same body exists on earth and in heaven and in between, then the claim that the body will be raised again seems to be impossible. To believe a doctrine which apparently presupposes something metaphysically impossible is tantamount to having an irrational18 belief. If a central element of Christian faith is irrational, then Christian faith will be at the very least severely impoverished in terms of its ability to be rationally justified. So Christians face the challenge of showing that their doctrine of bodily resurrection is not irrational. It is incumbent upon them to provide arguments which show convincingly that the gap between the annihilation of the human person in this world and her bodily resurrection in the next world can19 be bridged.

Bridging the Gap
  1. It was very early that Christian theologians offered a way to meet this challenge: after death the body decays but the last material particles constituting our body continue to exist. On the Last Day, God gathers up these very last material particles which once constituted our body and reassembles them into a new heavenly body which he then rejoins with the surviving soul. So body and soul once more constitute the same single human person who once existed on earth. Brian E. Daley calls this view "anthropology of composition": in order to be raised there must be both material and spiritual identity between the earthly and heavenly person20.
  2. One problem with this view is that particles constituting one body at t1 might constitute another body at t2. Take, for instance, the often discussed example of cannibalism: if a cannibal eats a fellow human person, so he incorporates particles into his body which formerly belonged to another body. On the resurrection day both the cannibal and his victim shall be raised again. But there are certain particles belonging to both bodies: how shall God proceed? God has to decide first who owns which particles. There are a few possible criteria: the first body has priority over all successive bodies to which a given particle belonged. Or the last body has priority over the previous ones. Or female bodies over male bodies or saints over sinners or believers over non-believers. The apparent problem is that there are no obviously objective criteria for deciding, leaving God to solve this puzzle arbitrarily21. In a second step, then, the missing particles have to be replaced with newly created ones. Then, however, no resurrected body with new particles is identical to the earthly body, strictly speaking. Athenagoras, a Christian apologist from the second century, was well aware of this problem. He invokes medical reasons for solving it. According to him each animal has a food suited to its nature. Only appropriate parts of the food can be absorbed so as to remain permanently in an animal’s body. Human beings cannot absorb human flesh, for it is not suitable to them. So, the particles constituting a human body could never end up as particles constituting another fellow human person's body as well. In a similar vein, early rabbis taught that an indestructible part of the spinal cord will be the toehold for the reconstruction of the resurrection body22.
  3. There are good reasons to look for other models of bodily resurrection. As far as we know, neither Athenagoras' nor the rabbi's accounts work23: there are no incorruptible parts of the human body and it is possible that certain particles belong to more than one human body. In the light of the length of human history it is even very probable to assume that some particles making up human bodies now belonged to other bodies previously.
  4. Peter van Inwagen came up with a different approach for avoiding these problems24. On their deaths men apparently cease to exist and human bodies apparently decompose. At the moment of each human person's death God clandestinely removes the dying person, whom He replaces with a simulacrum which falls prey to the natural destiny of material things: it rots and decays. The person, however, continues to live or is revivified in eternity. The problem of the gap does not arise, giving way instead to just the sort of miraculous intervention which an almighty God could enact. Such an intervention, however, would at any rate be necessary to guarantee the resurrection of an entity which is not immortal by nature. According to van Inwagen, nothing in the creeds contradicts his story. The downside of this model is that it requires God systematically to deceive human beings. Van Inwagen speculates that one reason for so much divine trickery might be God's will to leave enough freedom for voluntary faith. Imagine that a world in which the body-snatching scenario were apparent to all: in such a world all would believe in the existence of God for the simple reason that God's existence would amount to the best explanation for the observed phenomenon of body-snatching.
  5. Van Inwagen's solution for the problems plaguing the reassembly theory is ingenious. Nevertheless, serious troubles remain: the body-snatching model seems to imply either that no person ever dies, strictly speaking, or that resurrection amounts to a process similar to reanimation. If we interpret van Inwagen's model in the former sense, then the dying person is brought to heaven where she continues to live in a transformed and glorified way. Such a story, however, apparently contradicts the Christian doctrine that human persons truly die. The creeds confess that Jesus suffered death and was buried. There is no hint in these documents that these statements should not be taken at face value. In the latter sense, instead, the corpse is brought to heaven and brought back to life again. This gives the event of resurrection a very "biological touch". Human persons seem to be bound indissolubly to the body they had at the moment of death and the continuance of the biological functioning of the body seems to be all that truly matters for resurrection. Resurrection comes close to the reanimation of the deceased, along the lines of the resurrections reported in the gospels of Lazarus and of Jairus' daughter.
  6. In order to avoid some of the problems beleaguering van Inwagen's approach, Dean Zimmerman came up with the so called "falling elevator model25”. Zimmerman’s idea was to use van Inwagen's materialist metaphysics of human persons while developing a model by which God is able to raise human persons again without secretly replacing their dying body with a simulacrum. According to this metaphysics it is essential for human persons that they are organisms; the matter constituting an organism is caught up in a special event — a Life — which continues as long as the organism exists. Life is self-maintaining, that is, earlier stages in a Life tend to cause their successive stages. This process of continuous causation is direct and immanent; the immanent causal relations cannot pass through anything external to the organism, such as a teleportation machine. It is imaginable that one's psyche can pass through such a device and reappear elsewhere in a new organism. But it is hard to see how a material organism could survive such a procedure; all that could be accomplished is the generation of a duplicate organism formed, from the original pattern, either out of old or new particles. Given this framework, Zimmerman proposes the following solution: God could endow the particles constituting a human organism with a miraculous "budding" power. In the moment of death the particles continue to immanently-cause later stages in the existence of these particles on the one hand. The dying body becomes a corpse in a process we are familiar with. But, on the other hand, thanks to the budding power, in the next world the organism reappears. So the living organism goes one way, ending up in the next world, and at the same time the particles of the very same organism immanently cause a corpse in this world. The particles undergo a kind of fission process while the organism's Life remains one and the same.
  7. Zimmerman's approach avoids positing massive deception on God's part. The matter of the human body stays in this world. Nevertheless, nagging doubts remain about this approach. David B. Hershenov pointed out that in normal life-processes new particles gradually get integrated in the organism's body26. Zimmerman's budding event does not allow for a slow replacement of old particles over certain period of time but is more reminiscent of a very unusual birth scenario. He concludes:
      The entity in heaven is a clone of the deceased, and thus Zimmerman's account provides us with no more immortality than that which comes from an identical twin surviving our death. And whatever consolation that may give us as we are dying, it is not a case of true immortality27
  8. If I understand him correctly, Hershenov objects that Zimmerman's account is unable to guarantee personal identity strictly speaking. All we are left with is a kind of a closest continuer theory. The organism showing up in the next world is the closest continuer of the organism that died in this world. The corpse cannot be said to be the closest continuer of the organism that died, for it is essential to an organism to be alive and the only organism alive in this story is the one in the next world. To do justice to Zimmerman's model it must be noted that Zimmerman is well aware of the problem of a closest continuer. However, he accepts it willingly. For Zimmerman this is simply the metaphysical price which attends a metaphysical framework such as van Inwagen's28.
  9. Those unwilling to pay the price of a closest continuer theory might embrace a four-dimensionalist materialist conception of the human person. According to this approach a human person is composed of various temporal parts. Different entities are able to share the same temporal parts. If a fission scenario occurs, then according to four-dimensionalism, it becomes apparent that there have been two entities all along sharing the same temporal parts till the fission event and then dividing up by occupying different temporal parts from this moment on. Imagine, for instance, the human person John, composed of temporal parts resulting from a lifetime of eighty years. According to four-dimensionalism, there is not one entity, Johnp, but rather at least two different entities, namely the human person Johnp, and the human organism of Johnp, alias Johnorg. The difficulty in distinguishing between these two entities stems from the fact that, during his earthly lifetime, the temporal parts making up Johnp are all shared by Johnorg.
  10. When Johnp dies, the linked lives of both entities, Johnp and Johnorg, come to an end. A fission event occurs: saying that Johnp is raised from the dead means Johnp is succeeded by another part, John living in eternity, alias Johne. So, it can be said that Johnp continues to live in heaven because of his successive part Johne. The organism Johnorg, instead, remains on earth and is followed by temporal parts resulting in Johnp's corpse, alias Johnc. Johne does not stage-share any of his temporal parts with a living human organism such as Johnorg; rather he has features of what the gospels report from the body of the risen Christ. How four-dimensionalist approaches account for the causal linkage between different temporal parts such as Johnp. and Johne, allowing these parts to form one persisting entity, is a matter of dispute which can be neglected at this point. It could be imagined that God commands there to be the right causal linkage.
  11. A four-dimensionalist approach in this vein can easily address the difficulties raised about the relation between the different pre- and post-resurrection bodies. Hud Hudson, defender of such an approach, writes:
      owing to this very liberal account of composition, our Four-Dimensionalist Universalist is in a unique position to claim that no matter how profound are the differences between two temporally non-overlapping items, we will always be correct in our supposition that there is some persisting object that has them each as temporal parts, for even when those items are wholly unlike one another and separated by a significant temporal gap, some continuant or other is trivially guaranteed by the Universalist consequence that any two temporally discontinuous things have a mereological sum29.
  12. According to such an approach the problem of personal identity mutates into a problem of different temporal parts overlapping in such a way that the mereological sum of these parts forms one single entity. Unquestionably the four-dimensionalist approach offers a very elegant solution to many metaphysical problems besetting the doctrine of bodily resurrection, especially the problem of gappy existence.
  13. But like every metaphysical theory, four-dimensionalism comes with a price many are unwilling to pay.
  14. Apart from peculiar metaphysical worries30, the main motivation for rejecting a four-dimensionalist solution comes probably from common sense: in everyday life we do not conceive of ourselves as sums of temporal parts. We experience ourselves not as four-dimensional space-time-worms but rather as three-dimensional beings. E.J. Lowe voices this assumption:
      And even if we accept that temporal-parts theories provide a unitary explanatory framework in which problems of qualitative change, fission, and vagueness can conveniently be dealt with, we have to wonder whether this is enough to justify our acceptance of an idea so apparently obscure and contrary to common sense as that of temporal parts31.
  15. In light of this criticism of four-dimensionalism the impression arises that each account of bodily resurrection comes with a high cost. Either people do not die literally, or the resurrected person is the closest continuer of the deceased person, or identity claims mutate into technical reflections about mereology. No solution is able to preserve identity in the strict sense.
  16. Maybe, someone might argue, bodily resurrection simply takes a miracle and no informative metaphysical conditions for explaining identity between the pre- and post-mortem body can be given. There are no metaphysical conditions justifying our belief about identity between earthly and heavenly human existence which do not already presuppose this very same identity for which they are claimed to be conditions. Thus, a modest agnosticism about the problem of personal identity and resurrections is appropriate.
  17. Trenton Merricks is the proponent of such an "agnostic approach". According to him we may have intuitions that the way in which laws of nature structure this-worldly occurrences necessarily excludes the possibility of personal identity over gaps. Do such intuitions, however, justify us in holding that there are no metaphysically necessary conditions for identity over time which can possibly span temporal gaps? This question does not refer to nomological but to modal intuitions. Unluckily, our capacities for discerning what is principally possible and impossible do not lead to clear judgements concerning personal identity — not even in this world, as the many well known thought experiments about fission-and fusion-cases show. Therefore, according to Merricks, a modest agnosticism is the most reasonable position regarding criteria of identity in general and the possibility of bodily resurrection in particular. Admittedly, it cannot be shown that a resurrected person satisfies a bodily criterion for identity with some deceased person. But this negative result is less alarming than is generally thought. Since we seem to lack clear criteria even in this world, Christian faith is no worse off than our ordinary assumptions about personal identity32.
  18. This philosophical conclusion is meager but it should not dishearten us. Belief in resurrection does not derive primarily from philosophical reflections about personal identity and temporal gaps but is the direct consequence of divine revelation. Merricks underlines:
      to the extent that revelation justifies belief in the resurrection, I think it also justifies belief in bodily identity across a temporal gap. So it likewise justifies the conclusion that there are no necessary conditions for bodily identity that cannot possibly be satisfied across a temporal gap33.
  19. At the end, all hope for bodily resurrection resides in God's promise to raise all human beings again as Jesus Christ was raised from the dead with a glorified body. This hope is not a desperate one, for it is reasonable to believe that God, an almighty and perfectly good being, would not make a promise that is beyond his power to keep. So we are justified in holding that bodily resurrection is possible even though it takes a miraculous divine intervention for accomplishing it. At this point the same question can be asked which concludes Mavrodes's article: "But who knows whether that is philosophy34?”

Theological Reservations
  1. Merricks's and Mavrodes's accounts might sound far too theological for many philosophers. Nevertheless, most theologians are purportedly rather dissatisfied with the accounts put forward by analytic philosophers. From a theologian's perspective, the accounts may be apt for solving certain metaphysical problems but they are inappropriate for genuine theological purposes. Here are some reasons why this might be so: as indicated already, a strong materialist conception of the human body levels the difference between this life and the next. If the same particles get reassembled , then the laws of nature, which are presupposed by the existence of particles in this world, probably ought to obtain in the afterlife as well. If human persons are necessarily biological organisms, then resurrection seems to be a divine form of re-animation and eternal life a kind of divine fountain of youth. To most theological ears this sounds too materialist, biological, and this-worldly. The British physicist and theologian John Polkinghorne makes this point very clear:
      It is not necessary, however, that the ‘matter' of these bodies should be the same matter as makes up the flesh of this present world. In fact, it is essential that is should not be. That is because the material bodies of this world are intrinsically subject to mortality and decay. If the resurrected life is to be a true fulfillment, and not just a repeat of an ultimate futile history, the bodies of that world-to-come must be different, for they will be everlastingly redeemed from mortality35.
  2. Many theologians would thus be pleased to see whether an alternative, less materialist, conception of bodily resurrection could be developed without converging into a version of Platonic or Cartesian soul-body-dualism. The theologian's desideratum conceives "of the person as ‘more than' the body, and as a ‘centred self' distinct in some ways from it and its experiences, without ever being separable from it36."
  3. Furthermore, such an alternative account ought to be essentially relational. So far, approaches in the analytic tradition appear to theologians to be individualistic and sell-engaged. After an analysis of anthropological approaches ranging from substance dualism to non-reductive physicalism, theologian Stuart Palmer comes to the conclusion that they all need further development in terms of "a holistic and relational understanding of personal identity37
  4. To sum up: the philosophical discussion explicates the problems concerning the nature of human persons, diachronic identity, and God's role in resurrection. Philosophers are aware that an omnipotent God could accomplish the resurrection of the body in other ways than those which their models propose. As philosophers, however, it is hard to come up with "more godlike" solutions, since this would transcend the field of philosophy. So theologians should take seriously the metaphysical problems which philosophers try to overcome with their models. They should aim at incorporating valuable philosophical insights in their own accounts and see whether more theologically appropriate models can be spelled out thereafter.

An Exceedingly Brief Suggestion How to Proceed
  1. In light of theology's wish list, the phenomenological tradition might help to avert the suspicion that the philosophical discussion of the metaphysics of resurrection is too materialist and self-centered. The phenomenological tradition distinguishes between the concept of the human body conceived as something a subject experiences directly because it is her body, and as a material entity describable from a scientific point of view. In the former sense the human body is something you know about subjectively. In the latter sense, instead, you perceive the human body as something objective. Now, the former approach to the human body is necessary for an adequate understanding of specific capacities of the human person such as first-person-perspective, self-representation, and subjectivity. The latter approach, according to phenomenology, is instead the consequence of a certain practice, such as that of seeing something that is by nature essentially subjective as an object in order to study it scientifically.
  2. This twofold approach avoids strong materialist conceptions of the human person. Phenomenology teaches us that the concept of bodily resurrection is the notion of an embodied human person not that of a physical body as accounted for in scientific theory. In other words: it does not contradict the creeds to claim that bodily resurrection requires embodiment but not the physical realization of one's body as we are familiar with it from this world. We do not need an "anthropology of composition" as the Church Fathers believed in order to account for bodily resurrection. Accordingly, to rise again with a transfigured body means that ascriptions of physical or biological qualities cease definitively.
  3. Embodiment suffices for conceiving of the human person as an individual who was fundamentally embedded in relationships on earth and still is so in the afterlife. The doctrine of the resurrection of the body underlines that the human person does not "pull off' her history and earthly existence in the afterlife. Rather, these become integral parts of the communal inter-personal reality which serves as the interpretation of the eschatological fulfilment of the cosmos. The basis for human personhood is not physical reality but embodied existence which is able to participate in a communal reality created and maintained by God. Following the theologian Karl Rahner, the notion of the body refers to the symbolic reality of man, that is, what a human person becomes because of a specific history and life.
  4. Embodiment indicates, so to speak, that human persons are not isolated "pure" souls but subjects whose nature is to forge experiences by entering into relationships and taking up a determinate perspective toward the world they occupy. The concept of embodied human person embraces both the notion of a human subject capable of experiences and that of experiences made by this very human subject, through which that subject becomes the kind of human subject she is.
  5. One might ask at this point how to conceive of embodiment if not in terms of physical realization. In all humility we can admit that we do not yet know. It seems reasonable to concede that we presently lack the conceptual resources for answering this question in detail: We live in a physical world and cannot clearly conceive either of an eschatologically transformed world in partial discontinuity with the actual one nor of ourselves as being bodily but non-physical.
  6. We can aim, however, to specify the conditions that must obtain in order for bodily resurrection to be metaphysically and theologically feasible. This task leaves room for creativity to develop different sorts of models which meet these conditions. Such models indicate that an informative defense of the doctrine of resurrection is available even though we are not in a position to specify which mechanisms God actually uses for raising us from the dead38.
  7. The contributions in this volume follow this line of reasoning. They dispute the claim that bodily resurrection from the dead is a metaphysical impossibility by offering possible scenarios in which it occurs. These scenarios are a lively expression of the old dictum fides quaerens intellectum. They neither prevent nor impugn the faith of those believers who trust that a God who created the cosmos ex nihilo can also sustain human persons in existence when the physical world as it is known comes to an end. On the contrary, such scenarios can aid believers in considering more precisely which prospects for accomplishing this feat are the most promising. All the same time, non-believers are not exempt from considering these possible scenarios: Even if they do not see it as a matter of existential importance, reflecting on the scenarios put forward presents a provocative intellectual journey. It stretches the imaginative powers in thinking about what might happen to us after our earthly existence comes to an end.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: Introduction")

Footnote 1: My usual objection to the use of this quotation in the context of books such as this is that while Paul’s argument appears sound, the possibility of a general resurrection, while sufficient for Christ’s resurrection, is not necessary. There may be special circumstances involved in Christ’s resurrection that don’t apply in the general case. Ignoring Christ as a special case per se, his resurrection is one where there is bodily continuity which is lacking in the general case. Hence, Christian materialists have an easier time explaining the resurrection of Jesus than they do of those whose bodies are utterly destroyed. So, while it’s true that if resurrection is impossible, then Christ has not been raised, Christ’s resurrection as a demonstration of the possibility of resurrection has nothing metaphysically to say about the possibility of resurrection in the general case. Click here for Note for my developing thoughts on Resurrection.

Footnote 2: Stephen T. Davis, "The Counterattack of the Resurrection Sceptics. A Review Article", Philosophia Christi, 8 (2005): pp. 39-63, p. 40.

Footnote 3: Despite Wolterstorff’s resons that follow, I’m suspicious that it’s just the case that more Christians have found their way into academic philosophy, in the USA at least, though Woltersdorff is probably right as to the reasons contemporary analytic philosophy is more conducive to Christians than it was in the mid-20th century. I’ve read a paper on this – asking atheistic philosophers to stand up and be counted – but have forgotten what it is. It may be "Smith (Quentin) - The Metaphilosophy of Naturalism", or something else by its author.

Footnote 4: Nicholas Woltersdorff, "How Philosophical Theology Became Possible with the Analytic Tradition of Philosophy", in Oliver D. Crisp and Michael C. Rea (eds), Analytic Theology. New Essays in the Philosophy of Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 155-68.

Footnote 5: The usual objection to LP in this context is that the verification principle is itself unverifiable, so is nonsense by LP’s own lights. This may be correct, but LP ought to be repaired to be a theory of truth rather than of meaning. It is healthy to ask that for a statement to have claims to truth, there ought to some evidence – either logical or empirical – in its favour. But there are many meaningful but unverifiable statements. The LPs were also unduly pessimistic about the possibility of meaningful metaphysics, though they were right (as was Hume) to be suspicious of unrestrained metaphysical speculation.

Footnote 6: Is this Reformed Epistemology, as developed by Plantinga (see "Sudduth (Michael) - Reformed Epistemology and Christian Apologetics").

Footnote 7: Wolterstorff., p. 167.

Footnote 8: Such pluralism seems a step back from following the truth where it leads. Philosophers seem to be incorporating alien principles into analytic philosophy. I suppose a cornerstone of analytic philosophy was a commitment to naturalism, which does beg the question against the theists (if not deists). What we get are believers who (allow themselves to) see no problems with theism – and view their role as at least partly apologetic – and unbelievers who take the opposite stance. I suppose there are many neutral areas where there can be a meeting of minds. But philosophy – by its very nature – questions everything, while any ideological commitment protects some or many doctrines from criticism. Faith is by its very nature anti-philosophical.

Footnote 9: Not quite! It seems to me that all the contributors are Christians with the exception of Eric Olson, so this book is hardly a balanced presentation. I don’t know Olson’s faith-stance, if any, but as an animalist he can’t be open to the possibility of resurrection.

Footnote 10: No doubt the notion of resurrection was alien to Platonists, who looked for release from the body, but just what did Tertullian find “impossible” in the idea of resurrection?

Footnote 11: I’ve noted above the special case that is Jesus’ resurrection, because of some form of physical continuity between the pre- and post-mortem bodies. But, if Olson is right, we still have “gappy” existence – because “we” will never be identical to a corpse, as we (organisms) and corpses (masses of matter) have different persistence conditions. So, even in Jesus case, there is a period of discontinuity.

Footnote 12: Why “spirit” rather than “soul”? Just what is (a person’s) spirit in Christian theology? Is it just a life-principle, with no “personality” to it? “Into thy hands I commend my spirit.” Do individual persons have individual spirits? Why no mention of the “revolution” forged by Oscar Cullmann, in returning the focus to bodily resurrection, in – for example – "Cullmann (Oscar) - Immortality of the Soul or Resurrection of the Dead?"?

Footnote 13: Metamorphosis (Click here for Note) – is a tricky notion. There’s a distinction between qualitative change of a quantitatively self-identical thing (a human body) and a metamorphosis of one kind into another (frog to prince). A resurrection body (presumably) has different persistence conditions to the pre-mortem one – so cannot be of the same kind (or so it is said: Click here for Note, Click here for Note).

Footnote 14: Death (Click here for Note) – when not used metaphorically – is the permanent cessation of biological function. I assume such locutions as “I died on the operating table” – referring to the temporary cessation of heartbeat – as being figures of speech for dramatic effect. The real death of all human beings (and of Jesus) is important – but quite what Christian theology makes of it is unknown to me. Biological understanding is of fairly recent development. In Christian theology, death is important as the promised consequence of Adam’s sin upon all human beings (whatever is made of that), and is presumably associated with the separation of spirit from body.

Footnote 15: Some Christians would deny this and look for resurrection on a renewed Earth (at least for some humans – eg. the Jews – if not for they themselves). There seem to be two points here. First, that death is (in some sense, ie. in the absence of resurrection) the end of the individual. The second is that – given that we “are” in some sense bodily organisms of which (in general) nothing remains post-mortem – there is no hope for the resurrection of the very same individual.

Footnote 16: So, no Luz bone — I cover this in various Notes (Click here for Note, Click here for Note, and Click here for Note).

Footnote 17: Is there more to this principle than “Origin Essentialism” – that a thing’s origin is one of its essential characteristics, so couldn’t be other than it was. Hence Kripke’s argument that I couldn’t have been born at a time other than I was – though maybe this has to do with the composition of the zygote, so it’s not metaphysically impossible. See "Kripke (Saul) - Naming and Necessity: Lecture III", "Robertson (Teresa) - Possibilities and the Arguments for Origin Essentialism" and "Wilson (Jack) - Beyond Horses and Oak Trees: A New Theory of Individuation for Living Entities". Or is it a consequence of Leibniz’s Law?

Footnote 18: Can any philosopher believe something he knows to be irrational? Isn’t this tantamount to the reverse of Moore’s paradox (“I know Y is true, but I don’t believe it”) – “I believe X but not-X”? No doubt the line would go that X is not false as such, but something the truth of which I (benighted intellect that I am) can see no way of justifying.

Footnote 19: ”Can” is rather a loose word here. There’s no promise or expectation of a convincing solution to the problem. Zimmerman and Van Inwagen seem happy provided they can come up with any old “solution”, however unlikely, to bridge the gap – and leave the correct solution up to God.

Footnote 20: Brian E. Daley, "A Hope for Worms", in Ted Peters, Robert J. Russell and Michael Welker (Eds), Resurrection. Theological and Scientific Assessments (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans, 2002), pp. 136-64, p. 148.

Footnote 21: Just what’s the problem here? The “theory” is that a person is identical to the (suitably ordered) set of particles (plus the soul) that once made up that person (in this case, at the moment of death). But there is no such set that is “owned” by a person throughout life. I’m not too worried about God “arbitrarily” making up the numbers of particles by choosing similar ones as he sees fit, if “enough” were available to form the basis. But this model of identity just won’t do. There might be no particles in my body aged 90 that were in my body aged 2, yet I would have remained the same person.

Footnote 22: Caroline Walker Bynum, The Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, 200-1336 (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), p. 55.
… See "Bynum (Caroline) - Resurrection of the Body in Western Christianity, 200 - 1336"

Footnote 23: So these “theories” fail empirically. There are no problems in the assimilation of human flesh, and there are no “Luz bones”. Athenagoras’s theory would seem to fail even if true in the immediate sense. God would have to mark each particle so that if a worm ate human flesh, and a bird ate the worm, then that part of the bird would then not be capable of being assimilated by human digestion. I’m unclear how “Luz bones” were supposed to work. Would that mean that I am really, when it comes down to it, my Luz bone? Sounds even worse than saying that I am really my brain.

Footnote 24: Peter van Inwagen, "The Possibility of Resurrection", International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 9 (1978): pp. 114-21, reprinted in Paul Edwards (ed.), Immortality (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books 1997), 242-6.
… See "Van Inwagen (Peter) - The Possibility of Resurrection"

Footnote 25: Dean Zimmerman, "The Compatibility of Materialism and Survival: The "Falling Elevator Model", Faith and Philosophy, 16 (1999): pp. 194-212.

Footnote 26: David Hershenov, "Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection", Religious Studies, 38 (2002): pp. 451-69, pp. 460-3.
… See "Hershenov (David) - Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection"

Footnote 27: Hershenov, p. 463.

Footnote 28: See Zimmerman's article in this volume (Chapter 2).
… See "Zimmerman (Dean) - Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited"

Footnote 29: Hud Hudson, A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2001), p. 190.
… See "Hudson (Hud) - A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person"

Footnote 30: See, for instance, Michael Rea, "Temporal Parts Unmotivated", The Philosophical Review, 107 (1998): pp. 225-60.
… "Rea (Michael) - Temporal Parts Unmotivated"

Footnote 31: Ernest Jonathan Lowe, A Survey of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 57.
… See "Lowe (E.J.) - A Survey of Metaphysics"

Footnote 32: A very similar point was made by George Mavrodes, "The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity", Nous, 11 (1977): pp. 27-39.
… See "Mavrodes (George I.) - The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity"

Footnote 33: Trenton Merricks, "The Resurrection of the Body", in Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 476-90, P. 481.

Footnote 34: Mavrodes, "Life Everlasting", p. 39.
… See "Mavrodes (George I.) - The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity"

Footnote 35: John Polkinghorne, Science and Theology: An Introduction (London and Minneapolis: SPCK and Fortress, 1998), pp. 115-16.

Footnote 36: Paul S. Fiddes, The Promised End. Eschatology in Theology and Literature (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000), P. 91.

Footnote 37: Stuart Palmer, "Christian Life and Theories of Human Nature", in Joel B. Green and Stuart L. Palmer (eds), In Search of the Soul. Four Views of the Mind-Body-Problem (Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press, 2005), pp. 189-215, p. 214. On the importance of relationships for an appropriate theological anthropology see also Alistair I. McFayden, The Call to Personhood. A Christian Theory of the Individual in Social Relationships (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)."

Footnote 38: Christian Tapp highlights this point in his contribution in this volume (Chapter 12).
… See "Tapp (Christian) - Joseph Ratzinger on Resurrection Identity"



"Haag (Johannes) - Personhood, Bodily Self-Ascription, and Resurrection: A Kantian Approach"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Haag defends the claim that ascribing states of consciousness to ourselves is only possible if we are able to apply to ourselves predicates signifying bodily states as well. Understood as a transcendental thesis, this means that bodily self-ascription is an enabling condition for self-ascribing states of consciousness. This transcendental thesis unfolds by way of reference to the philosophical work of I. Kant, G. Evans, and P.F. Strawson. In light of these results, Haag asks which concepts of embodiment and self-reference underlie the eschatological transformation of the human person.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Haag (Johannes) - Personhood, Bodily Self-Ascription, and Resurrection: A Kantian Approach")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Hudson (Hud) - Multiple Location and Single Location Resurrection"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Hudson's approach depends on recent metaphysical considerations about the relation between space-time regions and the objects occupying them. The basic insight says that a resurrected human person might he conceived as an entity located either in two different space-time regions or in one scattered region with two (salient) temporally connected parts. On this view, the whole human being consists of a terrestrial part on the one hand and of a celestial part on the other hand with different spatio-temporal properties accordingly. Though this approach comes packaged with costs of its own, the resulting metaphysical framework may turn out to be of considerable interest to theologians for being able to account for personal identity though partial discontinuity.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Hudson (Hud) - Multiple Location and Single Location Resurrection")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Michaud (Derek) - Review of "Personal Identity and Resurrection: How do we Survive our Death?" Edited by Georg Gasser"

Source: The Heythrop Journal Volume 54, Issue 2, March 2013 Pages 330–331


Author’s Conclusion
  1. While uniformly insightful, the essays making up this collection generally suffer from a cluster of closely related, but by no means fatal, shortcomings.
    1. First, there is little evidence of an appreciation for the (potentially) symbolic nature of the creedal affirmation of bodily resurrection. Expressed another way, are the authors correct in their assumption to be speaking on behalf of the Christian view?
    2. Second, the authors fail to take even a cursory glance at popular culture or the platitudes and practices of loved ones at funerals, which indicate a dualistic model of the soul’s escape from the body and immediate transferal to heaven (or otherwise). The apparent dominance of this view among both practicing and nominal Christians begs for more consideration of the rationale for this project (i.e., creedal orthodoxy).
    3. Third, despite the stated goal of providing a philosophical account of the rationality resurrection there are a surprising number of appeals to what amounts to miracles to be found in this collection.
    4. Finally, it seems that granting the usefulness (or necessity) of this project is to already concede most of what is to be demonstrated. While Gasser is very clear about the intention of his collection to take the doctrine of the resurrection as its starting point why not simply continue to operate within the sphere of theology? How rational an account can one provide (and in what sense, “rational”?) when one has already taken for granted that resurrection is subject to a rational account?
  2. In short, like most well-crafted works in the philosophy of religion, this collection leads to reflection on its topic but also on the nature of the field and its relationship to theology as well. In this lies the highest strength of Gasser’s collection and its authors’ greatest gift to their reader.


COMMENT:



"Niederbacher (Bruno) - The Same Body Again? Thomas Aquinas on the Numerical Identity of the Resurrected Body"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Niederbacher discusses Thomas Aquinas’s influential teaching about bodily resurrection. Apparently there are two rival views in Aquinas's teaching, one more materialist, the other more dualist. The materialist says: what makes for the numerical identity of the body is that some elemental parts of which the body is composed during the earthly life will be part of the resurrected body. The dualist says: what makes for the numerical identity of the body is nothing other than the substantial form. Whenever the substantial form is embodied, this body will be of its flesh. Niederbacher argues that Aquinas should opt for the "dualist" view, in order to maintain the consistency of his overall account and to meet systematic objections.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Niederbacher (Bruno) - The Same Body Again? Thomas Aquinas on the Numerical Identity of the Resurrected Body")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Olson (Eric) - Immanent Causation and Life After Death"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010
Write-up Note1

Author’s Abstract
  • The paper concerns the metaphysical possibility of life after death.
  • It argues that the existence of a psychological duplicate is insufficient for resurrection, even if psychological continuity suffices for personal identity. That is because our persistence requires immanent causation.
  • There are at most three ways of having life after death:
    1. If we are immaterial souls;
    2. If we are snatched bodily from our deathbeds; or
    3. If there is immanent causation ‘at a distance' as Zimmerman2 proposes – but this requires an ontology of temporal parts3.

Sections
  1. Life After Death
  2. The Irreversibility Principle
  3. Souls and Body-Snatching
  4. The Psychological-Duplication Model
  5. Immanent Causation
  6. Some Consequences
  7. In Defence of Immanent Causation
  8. The Ontic-Leap Model
  9. The Divine-Command Model
  10. Worries
  11. The Four-Dimensional Divine-Command Model


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Olson (Eric) - Immanent Causation and Life After Death")

Footnote 2: Presumably this ought to be "Zimmerman (Dean) - Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited", though only Zimmerman’s earlier paper is cited in the Bibliography.

Footnote 3: Is this necessarily a fatal objection? 4-dimensionalism offers attractive solutions to many conundrums concerning fission.



"Quitterer (Josef) - Hylomorphism and the Constitution View"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    By analyzing the problems which bodily resurrection poses for the Constitution View of persons, Quitterer concludes that Hylomorphism encounters similar problems. He proposes reformulating the Scholastic concept of the soul as the basic capacity for everything that goes into a human being's life, including the capacity to have a first-person perspective. He argues that the advantage of this approach over the Constitution View lies in the fact that the explanation proffered by the soul embraces both mental and bodily functions. Thus, within a Hylomorphic framework, it belongs to the inner logic of the concept of the soul to guarantee not only the survival of a first-person perspective but the resurrection of the body as well.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Quitterer (Josef) - Hylomorphism and the Constitution View")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Russell (Robert John) - Scientific Insights into the Problem of Personal Identity in the Context of a Christian Theology of Resurrection and Eschatology"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Russell asks how the belief in individual eschatology affects our understanding of' the eschatological transformation of all reality. If bodily resurrection means Transformation (and not resuscitation or spiritual flight), and if transformation includes elements of continuity against a deeper background of discontinuity at the matter side of creation, then there must be some elements of continuity and discontinuity in reality as we now know it. Russell presents possible models of continuity and eschatological transformation of the cosmos by taking into consideration cosmological conceptions of space-time on the one hand and theological models on the other hand.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Russell (Robert John) - Scientific Insights into the Problem of Personal Identity in the Context of a Christian Theology of Resurrection and Eschatology")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Schartl (Thomas) - Bodily Resurrection: When Metaphysics Needs Phenomenology"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    This paper combines the analytic debates on the metaphysics of resurrection with insights from phenomenology. Schartl argues that phenomenology helps to develop a clearer notion of the raised "spiritual body" following the notion of "natural body": A natural body is not understood primarily as an object describable entirely by science but as the object of our direct perception and our primary experience. The point is that the human person has to be "embodied" in order to exist but it is not necessary for it to be physically embodied. Finally, Schartl indicates how his combination of analytic metaphysics and phenomenology might contribute to an amended version of the "resurrection in death" theology as well.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Schartl (Thomas) - Bodily Resurrection: When Metaphysics Needs Phenomenology")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Tapp (Christian) - Joseph Ratzinger on Resurrection Identity"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Tapp elaborates cornerstones for a Christian understanding of eschatology. He does so by analyzing the scholarly work on eschatology of the current pope of the Roman Catholic Church, Benedict XVI. He emphasizes the following points:-
    1. the resurrected body is transformed but is somehow identical to our natural body; resurrection thus means fulfillment and perfection for the material aspects of the world;
    2. the traditional scholastic concept of the "human soul" is valuable for systematic theological discourse if "purified" from strong dualist commitments;
    3. the ultimate fulfilment of man is dialogical and relational both to other human beings and to God.
    Thus, Christian eschatology essentially has a communitarian aspect.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Tapp (Christian) - Joseph Ratzinger on Resurrection Identity")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Wandinger (Nikolaus) - The Rationale behind Purgatory"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    According to Wandinger's approach, on the "day of wrath" the prosecution's part is played by the victims of evil actions themselves. Extrapolating from human interaction as we know it, it seems very likely that the encounter of victims and culprits will result in mutual accusations. If heaven is the harmonious community between God and all the humans saved, then only those who have ended their mutual accusation can enter into it. Wandinger asks which features of the human person are essential to such an interpretation of purgatory and the salvific actions of God. He points at the importance of being embodied, enjoying a first-person-perspective, having certain standards of rationality, and the ability of human and divine persons to enter into relationships.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Wandinger (Nikolaus) - The Rationale behind Purgatory")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser



"Zimmerman (Dean) - Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited"

Source: Gasser (Georg) - Personal Identity and Resurrection: How Do We Survive Our Death? 2010


Abstract1
    Zimmerman's falling elevator model is widely discussed within the metaphysics of resurrection. In this paper Zimmerman explains in detail his attitude towards the model, including his thought about human organisms. Then he responds to objections raised against the model by William Hasker, David Hershenov, and Eric Olson. He argues that the model is still one way in which God could accomplish that the resurrected body represents a continued life of the earthly body despite the criticisms raised.

Full Text
  1. The resurrection of the dead would doubtless be a miraculous event. But some have claimed that not even a miracle would suffice. Given certain conceptions of the body that is to be resurrected, it can seem flat out contradictory to claim that human bodies have a destiny beyond the accidents and diseases that at least appear to end our earthly lives.
  2. More than thirty years ago, Peter van Inwagen wrote a paper that became the focus for much subsequent discussion of the doctrine of resurrection2. Van Inwagen did two things: he made a particularly clear case for the impossibility of resurrection; and then he told a story intended to show a way in which God could, after all, succeed in resurrecting every human body that has ever died. The story involved a kind of secret policy of "body-snatching" on God's part: God surreptitiously takes (at least a large part of) each body just as it dies. Elsewhere, out of sight, these bodies are kept alive, healed, and in other ways improved, to prepare them for the New Creation.
  3. However useful the story might be as a way to show that the appearance of complete biological death is compatible with the resurrection of these very bodies, there is a downside to supposing the story is true. Large chunks of matter do not seem to disappear whenever a human being dies. If God actually used this method, He would be in the business of replacing our living bodies with dead simulacra, made of entirely new (or at least different, imported) material, at the last possible moment; and that would involve God in a sort of massive, systematic deception — roughly on the same scale as creating a "young earth" but hiding fake dinosaur bones in the ground to make it look as though our planet has an ancient and interesting history.
  4. Just how unseemly would it be for God to follow this policy of deception? I can imagine that God has reason to conceal, to some extent, the facts about our ultimate destinies — including whether bodily resurrection occurs. Perhaps our freedom to choose among morally weighty alternatives depends upon a failure to see, with complete clarity, all the ramifications of our choices3? A failure to know, with certainty, what happens at death might be a crucial part of the strategy God uses to shield us from some of the relevant facts. One way to hide the facts about the afterlife would be to deliberately deceive us about something — for example, by surreptitiously stealing our bodies at death4. Still, it would be nice to be able to see a way in which the resurrection could happen that did not involve quite so much trickery. It was in this context that I developed what I called "the Falling Elevator Model" of survival for living organisms, and offered it to van Inwagen as an alternative to his original model5.
  5. The Falling Elevator Model is so-called because it involves a last-second jump that saves us from what looks like certain death — a strategy sometimes used by cartoon characters when an elevator cable breaks and they are hurtling toward the subbasement. Reaction to the proposal was mixed. Hud Hudson and Kevin Corcoran said: "That's so crazy, it just might work!", making good use of it in their very different versions of Christian materialism6. Others thought it was merely crazy, and have criticized it from various perspectives. I begin by describing what the model was originally intended to do, and also what I hope the model can do. The bulk of the paper consists of responses to a series of important criticisms leveled against Falling-Elevator-style resurrection by William Hasker, David Hershenov, and Eric Olson.

The Original Setting: van Inwagen's Materialist Metaphysics
  1. I shall assume, throughout this paper, that the body to be resurrected is a living organism belonging to the species homo sapiens. For van Inwagen, there is a special urgency to the question whether such things survive the (apparent) deaths to which organisms are prone; for he believes that human persons simply are organisms, and can survive nothing that an organism cannot survive7. So the body-snatching model of how my body could escape its apparent demise is, from van Inwagen's point of view, a model of how I could survive apparent death. When he wrote "The Possibility of Resurrection", van Inwagen thought that there is no other way in which God could ensure that a dying human body be resurrected. But that was many years ago, when he was still just exploring the possibility of various Christian doctrines, and had not yet been convinced of their truth. For his purposes then, it was interesting to note that the body-snatching model established at least the possibility of the rejuvenation of these very bodies. But, for some time now, he has been open to the idea that there may be other ways to "accomplish the Resurrection of the Dead ... ways I am unable even to form an idea of because I lack the conceptual resources to do so8."
  2. Before sketching the proposal, I echo van Inwagen's remark: I believe that there are ways besides the Falling Elevator Model by means of which God could accomplish the resurrection of these very bodies, short of outright body-snatching. I have no confidence whatsoever that the way I suggest is anything close to what actually happens. As in St. Paul's day, skeptics ask: "How are the dead raised up? and with what body do they come?" (1Cor 15:35). What I offer is a “just-so" story intended to undermine the claim that the resurrection is simply impossible without massive deception on God's part. To the extent that the story works, it does so by stretching the imaginations of those who think there is no way it could be done. The fine details do not represent my own speculations about the mechanism God actually employs; so I can afford to be flippant, at various points. Anyone who takes me too seriously will deserve the response St. Paul gave to the resurrection-skeptics of his era: "Thou fool! ... ".

A Sketch of the Model
  1. Here are the bare bones of the Falling Elevator Model. I adopt van Inwagen's useful terminology, and take on board as many of his metaphysical assumptions as possible: whenever some matter constitutes an organism, there is a special kind of event, a Life, that occurs to the matter and that continues for as long as that organism exists. As bits of the matter are replaced by new material, the things participating in this Life change; but so long as the Life goes on, the organism continues to exist, no matter how much material change there has been. An essential feature of the Life of an organism is that it displays a kind of "self-maintenance", earlier stages in a Life tending naturally to cause later stages that closely resemble the earlier ones in crucial ways. Because of the self-perpetuating nature of its Life, an organism displays a distinctive sort of "immanent causation", its later stages causally dependent upon earlier stages. For an organism, the immanent causal dependencies must be direct — they cannot, for instance, pass through the computer banks of a teleportation device or a blueprint in God's mind. Some philosophers (though not van Inwagen) believe there are kinds of objects that can survive such episodes; according to many psychological continuity accounts of personal identity, for example, a person could be teletransported. Still, it sounds odd, at least, to say that the very same organism could be torn to bits by the teletransporter, only to reappear elsewhere when the device assembles a living body using new materials based on the same pattern. Van Inwagen thinks each of us just is an organism; whether or not that is so, I do not doubt that my body is just an organism; so, if this very body is to show up subsequent to (what appears to be) my death, its resurrection cannot be achieved simply by God's performing the function of a teletransporter — that is, using what He knows about the state of my body at death as a blueprint for assembling one that exactly resembles it. Such a body would not continue the Life of this one; it would be a new organism, a mere duplicate.
  2. The Falling Elevator Model is a way to allow the Life of a dying organism to go one way, while the dead matter goes another way. The trick is to posit immanent-causal connections that "jump" from the matter as it is dying, connecting the Life to some other location where the crucial organic structure of the organism is preserved. Immanent causation is not peculiar to organisms; all ordinary physical objects in which we take an interest are the kinds of things that exhibit causal dependencies of later stages upon earlier stages. This includes boring objects, like hunks of dead matter. If a pile of matter persists throughout a period of time, the existence and properties of the later stages of the matter must be partly causally dependent upon the existence and nature of the earlier stages. Since each bit of matter in my body is supposed to stay behind when I die, to be buried (or devoured or ...), there must also be immanent causal connections between the matter in the dying body and the dead material left behind — on pain of body-snatching. So every portion of the matter in my body undergoes something like fission at the time of my death. Consider just the atoms in my body; and pretend that my body consists entirely of atoms (and the parts of atoms). The Falling Elevator Model affirms that, at the moment of my death, God allows each atom to continue to immanently cause later stages in the "life" or history of an atom, right where it is then located, as it normally would do; but that God also gives each atom the miraculous power to produce an exact duplicate at a certain distance in space or time (or both), at an unspecified location I shall call "the next world". The local, normal, immanent-causal process linking each atom to an atom within the corpse is sufficient to secure their identities; no atom ceases to exist merely because it exercised this miraculous "budding" power to produce new matter in a distant location. Still, the arrangement of atoms that appears at a distance is directly immanent-causally connected to my body at the time of my death; and there are no other arrangements of living matter produced by my dying body that are candidates for continuing my Life. The atoms do something that resembles fissioning — though what they really do is more like "budding", producing exactly similar offspring in the next world — while the organism does not fission. My body's Life does not divide, but goes in one direction only, carrying my body with it to a new location.

My Stake in the Falling Elevator Model
  1. The Falling Elevator Model was originally developed as a sort of "five-finger exercise", an attempt to see whether I could come up with a way to make sense of the resurrection within constraints that made it extremely (and, by my lights, needlessly) difficult. I do not share van Inwagen's conviction that we are mere organisms. I do not claim to know what kind of thing we actually are, but I suspect that we may well be immaterial thinking things, generated by brains (and, in turn, able to think by means of complex interactions with brains9). There are philosophical arguments I accept that make such a position a live option; in fact, I believe they show it to have many advantages over the most popular versions of materialism10. And I find a dualist conception of human persons strongly favored by central theological traditions within Christianity — traditions to which I try to be as faithful as I can11. Given such a dualism, it is much easier to see how God could insure our survival. Even if souls are generated and sustained by neural activity, and so are not naturally immortal, they might nevertheless be preserved by God in an unnatural state, awaiting reunion with the (or a) body. Given the strong dualistic inclinations human beings largely share (inclinations that seem to go further back than the origins of today's major religions), one could hardly accuse God of massive deception if our survival of death were managed in this way. It is just the sort of thing that we, left to ourselves, tend to believe anyway!
  2. Still, I regard the Falling Elevator Model as more than an abstract exercise in van Inwagian metaphysics. Christian dualists must insist that disembodiment is at best a truncated, incomplete form of existence for human persons; we await the resurrection of the body and a renewal of the entire cosmos. And we are typically instructed to believe in the resurrection of this very body, a body that, to all appearances, shall one day decay in the grave (or be devoured by sharks or cannibals, or blown to smithereens at the center of a nuclear explosion, or subjected to one of the many other interesting fates frequently encountered in the literature on resurrection). So even a Christian dualist can have some motivation to believe in the resurrection of bodies that, to all appearances, are utterly destroyed.
  3. Not all philosophers have been as receptive as Corcoran and Hudson to the possibility of resurrection by a perfectly timed leap out of the various Falling Elevators awaiting us at the ends of our earthly lives12. In particular, Hasker, Hershenov, and Olson have raised important objections, to which I now turn.

Hasker and the Necessity of Identity
  1. Hasker's arguments against the Falling Elevator Model are complicated. But the general strategy is this: he points out that the Falling Elevator Model must include a "closest continuer" account of the persistence conditions of organisms. But any closest continuer theory will, he argues, do one of two things: either require the denial of the necessity of identity; or else lead to "other assumptions that are at least equally problematic". For details about these "other assumptions," he directs the reader's attention to Harold Noonan's book, Personal Identity13. My original paper had included an argument to the effect that, however much one might dislike the closest continuer theory, a materialist of van Inwagen's stripe must accept it in order to deal with cases of fissioning organisms. But Hasker disputes this claim as well; he offers van Inwagen a way to deny that the purported stories about fissioning (human) organisms represent cases in which the presence of a competitor makes a difference.
  2. My reply to Hasker has three parts:
    • (i) I explain why the Falling Elevator Model requires a closest continuer theory, and explicate the "only x and y" principle that is violated by such a theory;
    • (ii) I rebut Hasker's argument that a van Inwagen-style materialism can hold onto the "only x and y" principle; and
    • (iii) I argue that rejection of an "only x and y" principle is not nearly so problematic for materialists as Hasker makes it seem.
  3. Hasker describes the commitments of the closest continuer theorist in this way: "The question to be asked is whether it is consistent with the actual history of the surviving individual that there should be an ‘equal claimant' to identity with the person in the past14." Hasker's terminology is informal, but the intent is pretty clear. He is considering merely possible cases, so talk of "the actual history of the surviving individual" is shorthand for "the history of the individual in a world where it survives" from one time to another. According to Hasker, it could not be the case that that very same history occurs in some other possible world in which the presence of another individual makes a difference to the survival of the original individual. This thesis about persistence conditions is sometimes called "the only x and y principle", and can be tidied up a bit in this way:
      (OXY) There are no possible individuals x and y such that: (i) x persists from t to t* in some world w, (ii) y does not exist in w, (iii) the event which is the history of x between t and t* in w ("the actual history of x") could have occurred in a world w* in which y also existed, and (iv) because of y's presence in w*, x does not persist from t to t* in w*, but stops existing at some time between the two.
  4. As Harold Noonan has pointed out, if a principle like (OXY) is meant to rule out closest continuer theories, "the event which is the history of x between t and t*" must be carefully parsed. Closest continuer theorists want to say that events just like those that happen within the region occupied by a human organism throughout some period could have occurred, but have failed to constitute the life of a single individual simply because of things that happen elsewhere. If the event which is a particular organism's life essentially involves that organism, or essentially involves the absence of certain events elsewhere, then (OXY) can happily be accepted by the closest continuer theorist. (OXY) is only equivalent to the denial of a closest continuer theory if "history of x between t and t* in w" is understood in such a way that (1) it is not an event that could only happen to x, and (2) it does not imply anything about events outside of the region occupied by x between t and t*. Noonan respects (1) by stating his version of the principle in terms of the "hunks of matter" that constitute x throughout the period; and he respects (2) by appealing to the notion of "mere Cambridge changes". Some events happening to the hunks of matter constituting x will be extrinsic events ("mere Cambridge changes", like coming within five feet of a burning barn); but other events will he intrinsic to the matter — consisting only in what is going on within the region occupied by the matter. The same history that happens to x from t to t* in w will occur in w*, so long as the series of hunks of matter that constitute x during that period occupy the same regions from t to t* and undergo events intrinsically just like their counterparts in w15.
  5. There is good reason to think the Falling Elevator Model will require denial of (OXY). Imagine a world w1, just like the actual world except that, many years ago, God secretly caused my atoms to "bud", generating duplicates in the next world in just the way the Falling Elevator Model recommends that God do at my death – but in w1, I am not about to die, and the atoms in my body carry on with their terrestrial biological activities in the same way they did in the actual world. Since this budding happened during the middle of my childhood, in w1 a child appeared in the afterlife who remembers — or seems to remember — my childhood. On the face of it, the mere occurrence of this budding event should not have killed me as a child; I should have been able to survive having my atoms cause duplicates to appear far away in this manner, so long as the atoms in my body did not themselves do anything unusual, then and there. If I would not have survived this unnoticed childhood budding of my atoms, it could only have been because my survival is incompatible with one stage in my Life producing competing stages (even when one of the competitors is far away in space-time). But, in that case, (OXY) would be violated straightaway: for in w1 there is a history involving hunks of matter undergoing events that are intrinsically just like the events in my actual history; but in w1 I would be replaced by a duplicate at the undetectable point of budding merely because of something that happens outside the region in which that history occurs.
  6. Suppose, then, that in w1 I survive this childhood budding of my atoms. Now imagine a world w2 in which the budding occurs simultaneously with the destruction of my earthly atoms. The Falling Elevator Model implies that Zimmerman himself would thereby have leapt to the next world. But the same history that, in w2, constitutes a single person — childhood me and then the resurrected me — occurs in w1 and fails to constitute a single person. So, on this supposition, too, (OXY) is violated. Whatever one says about what happens in a childhood "budding", the Falling Elevator defender winds up affirming a closest continuer account of my persistence conditions: whether certain intrinsically similar events constitute the Life of a single person can depend upon events that happen outside of the places where the events in that Life actually occur.
  7. The argument is not airtight; some materialists can embrace the Falling Elevator Model without commitment to a closest continuer theory. Hud Hudson, in his ingenious use of the Falling Elevator story, shows how to avoid the closest continuer account of personal identity by tearing a page from David Lewis's book: cases of fission can be regarded as cases in which there were two things all along, sharing temporal parts prior to, but not after, the fission event. In the case of the childhood budding followed by my normal life and eventual resurrection, the child and I shared our childhood temporal parts; then, in the next world, we ceased to overlap. Whether or not a person had been allowed to continue in the time and place at which budding occurred, pre-budding stages plus child-like stages that appear in the next world would have constituted a single person; and (OXY) is not violated.
  8. Van Inwagen (like many other Christian materialists, including Peter Geach, Trenton Merricks, Kevin Corcoran, Lynn Rudder Baker, and Michael Rea) rejects the metaphysics of temporal parts that allows Hudson to sidestep the threat to (OXY) posed by childhood budding. I had argued that, whether or not van Inwagen accepts the Falling Elevator Model, the fact that organisms can undergo fission will force him to reject (OXY) and accept a closest continuer account of personal identity; so, for him, my Falling Elevator Model comes at no cost. Hasker, however, denies that my argument goes through; van Inwagen can, he says, affirm (OXY) in the face of the fission of a human-like creature.
  9. Here is why I thought van Inwagen would be forced to deny (OXY). The principle is hard to credit when applied to many actual organisms, such as bushes and certain worms, in which there can be symmetrical duplication of major organs, or diffuse, divisible, life-sustaining systems. When half of a bush (including half the roots) is pruned away, what is left is also a bush. One is tempted to say it is the original bush. But had the two halves simply been separated to make two different bushes, at most one can be identical with the original. Given their equal claims to be the original bush, and the implausibility of supposing there are "brute facts" about bush identity, the thing to say is that division in half, for a symmetrical organism, destroys it. The materialist who accepts (OXY), however, cannot say: if half the bush is kept alive, the original bush is destroyed; but if the same half had been removed and simultaneously killed, the original bush would have survived. For roughly symmetrical organisms that can live through large-scale loss of parts, the only principled way to draw the line would be: removing half the matter kills the organism, but less than half does not.
  10. Human beings are not perfectly symmetrical, of course. The cerebrum shows a surprising amount of symmetry, and we do seem able to survive with either hemisphere. Unlike the cerebrum, the brain stem is not divisible into two potentially independently functioning halves, nor is the heart. Nevertheless, our failures of symmetry would seem to be biological accidents, given duplication in so many other organs. If humans can have symmetrical brain hemispheres, human-like creatures could have symmetrical and divisible organs and systems along an entire plane of symmetry. What should the proponent of (OXY) say about creatures like us, but with divisible brain stems, hearts, and so on? Could such a creature lose half its matter, yet survive? Van Inwagen says it could not16. I argued that it is implausible for the materialist to take this line17. I will not repeat my objections here, because Hasker agrees: van Inwagen should have said that such a creature could survive the destruction of half its parts at once18. He offers van Inwagen a different response.
  11. Hasker's discussion involves Mark, a human-like creature whose cerebrum, brain stem, and so on are neatly divisible. Hasker thinks he has found a way for van Inwagen to maintain that:
    • (a) Mark could survive the destruction of half of his matter,
    • (b) fission along the same plane would result in Mark's death, and
    • (c) (OXY) is true.
    In the case in which half of Mark's cells are destroyed, Hasker claims that it is not "consistent with the actual history" of Mark that an "equal claimant" should have existed. The destruction of half of Mark's cells — the ones which, had they been carefully removed, would have constituted an equal claimant—is "an event in Mark's own life19".
  12. If this is to represent a way to save (OXY), the claim must be that the events undergone by the series of hunks of matter constituting Mark, in the world that includes destruction of half of his matter, cannot be paired up with intrinsically similar events undergone by a similar series of hunks of matter in a world where Mark undergoes fission. But I do not see why this must be so. Compare two surgeries: in one, an organ is cut away from a living body and simultaneously destroyed; in another, the organ is cut away in the same fashion but preserved for transplantation into another body. There need be no difference between the two surgeries, from the point of view of the hunks of matter constituting the patient's body before, during, and after the surgery; intrinsically, the events within the body of the patient will "look" exactly the same. Similarly, when considering just the region occupied by Mark's body, and the events that go on within it when half of its matter is cut away and simultaneously killed, I cannot see why a region just like that could not contain exactly similar matter undergoing exactly similar events, when the departing organs are cut away and preserved alive. It sounds as though Hasker is saying that the otherwise similar events occurring in the world where fission occurs would differ simply because, in that world, they would not happen to Mark. But allowing happening to Mark to count as something that is required for the same history to occur in the two worlds would trivialize (OXY), turning it into something a closest continuer theorist could easily accept.
  13. So Hasker has not provided a way for a van Inwagian materialist to avoid the closest continuer theory. But is Hasker right to think that a materialism committed to the closest continuer theory is utterly untenable?
  14. At some points Hasker seems to argue in this way: if a closest continuer theory of identity over time is accepted, one should have to admit that identity is contingent. But that is unacceptable.
      An "identity relation" that is merely contingent is not identity, and to accept a closest continuer theory for the persistence of persons is in effect to admit that no person is identical with a person that existed at an earlier period of her own life. And this is a price none of us should be willing to pay20.
  15. However, in a footnote to this sentence, Hasker grants that "there can be a version of the closest continuer theory that avoids making identity a contingent relation," but one that leads to "assumptions that are at least equally problematic."
  16. I agree that, if the closest continuer account leads to denial of the necessity of identity, it should be rejected. There is a familiar, plausible argument against contingent identities. Actual identity requires sharing all properties. And it is hard to deny that, for every x, necessarily, x is identical to x. But then Jones will have the property of being necessarily identical to Jones, Smith the property of being necessarily identical to Smith, and so on. Smith, then, could not be Jones without being necessarily identical to Jones; and so contingent identity is ruled out. There are ways to escape this line of reasoning, but Hasker and I accept it.
  17. Why think the closest continuer theory leads to denial of the necessity of identity? Consider the incidence of childhood budding described above — the example in which I survive and grow old, to meet my childhood offshoot in the next world who is not identical with me. It would be tempting, were I a materialist advocate of the Falling Elevator story, to imagine meeting the child and saying: "Had things gone differently — for example, had my matter been destroyed at the point of fission — I would have been identical with you. But, as it turns out, I am not identical with you." Most of Hasker's discussion of the Falling Elevator Model presumes that its advocate will have to accept the truth of some contingent identity statement along these lines21. But there is a simple way out for the materialist (a way out that Hasker recognizes, but only in footnotes22). Instead of saying that I could have been identical to the child, I should have said:
      Had my matter been destroyed at the point of budding, the matter which was caused to appear in the next world by the budding of the particles would have constituted me, and not this child. In those circumstances, this child would not have existed23.
  18. Though the child would not have existed, events would have occurred that are exactly like those that constituted the child's Life; a consequence some might find odd, but the closest continuer theorist is stuck with it.
  19. Hasker does not worry about this alternative to contingent identity, because he believes Noonan has shown it to be "at least equally problematic24." Noonan's problems for the view, however, do not seem to me to be nearly as bad as denying the necessity of identity. His discussion is subtle and extensive, but the main sort of troubling consequence is just this: the next-worldly child could rightly say to me, "Had your matter been destroyed at the time my matter was generated, I would never have existed, and you would now be composed of the matter that is, instead, constituting me." But how bad is this? Not nearly so dire as rejecting the necessity of identity. Yes, it is a violation of (OXY). But that alone should hardly shock the materialist. Those who reject (OXY) can point out that there is plenty of reason to doubt whether the presence of a single organism in a region throughout a period is ever an entirely intrinsic matter. Whether some matter constitutes a thing of a certain kind depends upon whether there is more matter attached to it. Let "Baldy" be the part of my body that does not include my hair. Baldy is not the whole organism; the whole organism includes at least the living parts of my hair. But if all my hair could die, and the rest of my body remain the same for any period of time, then something intrinsically just like Baldy could be an entire organism. Such examples are enough to overthrow (OXY) already; so, if Noonan's principle really isolates the most problematic commitment of closest continuer theories, it is a commitment that arises in very simple situations of the gain and loss of parts.
  20. It still seems to me, then, that the best option for the materialist who opposes temporal parts is: Learn to live with the closest continuer theory. Once one has done that, there should be no problems making use of the Falling Elevator Model — at least, none coming from violation of (OXY) and recognition of the relevance of "equal claimants" in the next world.

Hershenov and the Assimilation Principle
  1. The Falling Elevator Model implies that an organism can lose all of its tiniest parts at once, replacing them with entirely new matter. David Hershenov argues that this is not possible25. In the normal course of things, new matter is assimilated by a body gradually. "There is an overlap of the new and the old, and this enables the new particles to be assimilated into the individual's body." Hershenov claims that this is essential to assimilation; new parts can only be taken on board in the presence of many old parts. And so, "when every part of the body fissions, as Zimmerman postulates, there is no assimilation of new particles and cells to earlier ones26." Thus the resurrected body is a duplicate, constituted by brand new matter that never had a chance to become part of my body.
  2. The exact formulation of Hershenov's assimilation principle is important. I might be able to accept an assimilation principle that merely rules out the possibility of an organism's losing all of its proper parts at the same time. Suppose that, as a matter of necessity, whenever a living thing dies, there are some proper parts that also cease to exist (for example, cells or organs that perish along with the organism). I am not at all sure whether this is true. But if it were, then, so long as the resurrection jump works for the organism as a whole, it ought to succeed in bringing these proper parts into the next world as well. And therefore, whenever a living thing survives death by means of the falling elevator method, some proper parts of it will also survive. Hershenov's assimilation principle is clearly meant to require much more than just some continuity of proper parts whenever new parts are acquired. In the normal case, he says:
      new particles ... get caught up in life processes with some old particles while other particles that were already part of the organism are exhaled, excreted, and perspired. There is an overlap of the new and the old [particles], and this enables the new particles to be assimilated into the individual's body.... [But] when every part of the body fissions, as Zimmerman postulates, there is no assimilation of new particles and cells to earlier ones27.
  3. A crucial advantage of the Falling Elevator story is that, at some level of scale, the matter in my body stays in this world. Whatever is involved when any hunk of matter "stays put" in the ordinary way, that same sort of (boring) process happens in the space-time region occupied by my body at death and my corpse afterwards. Now, it is a vexed question how (and, indeed, whether) ordinary matter persists through time, especially at the subatomic level. Hershenov's talk of "particles" suggests that he is accepting a presupposition of my original account: ultimately, every physical object is completely decomposable into a set of partless particles. I, in turn, made this assumption because it is part of van Inwagen's metaphysics of composite objects. Personally, I should rather leave it an open question whether we are made of persisting simples — a question to be settled, if it can be settled at all, by physics. The assumption of ultimate simple parts is problematic because the most fundamental description of physical systems may well be hard to interpret in terms of spatially restricted, minimal parts. I know of no compelling argument for the impossibility of infinitely divisible homogeneous matter, for example; so I suppose the metaphysician has no business ruling it out as impossible. This should not stop us talking about parts and wholes, but it might undermine the idea that there is some bottom level of simplest parts. So I shall try to develop an assimilation principle that does not presuppose that every physical object is decomposable without remainder into simple particles.
  4. The notion "decomposition without remainder" is useful in articulating assimilation principles:
      (D) x is decomposable without remainder into the objects in S =df every member of S is a part of x, and every part of x has at least one part in common with some member of S.
  5. Here is a first stab at an assimilation principle that would undermine the Falling Elevator Model.
      (AP1) If x persists through some finite period leading up to, but not including, t, then, if x exists at t, it is not then completely decomposable without remainder into a set of things none of which was part of x before t.
  6. This first stab is not so good, because it does not say enough about the scale of the parts in the complete decomposition. Some metaphysicians believe there are such things as mere hunks of matter — for example, the matter now making up the top half of my body and the matter now making up the bottom half. If there are such things, they are the kind of thing that cannot gain or lose any bits of matter; it is a truism that, if some of the matter in my body is taken away or some new matter added, I am no longer constituted by exactly the same matter — but rather by just some of the matter, or by some new portion of matter that includes the old matter as a part. So take two hunks of matter a and b that together make up all of my body prior to some time t; and add some atoms to a to produce a* and to b to yield b*. At t there is a set of things, namely the set containing just a* and b*, which is a complete decomposition of my body at t. Yet neither of the two was part of my body prior to t. So (AP1) implies that I cannot survive this; but there really should be no problem with assimilating the two atoms that were added to a and b — there are plenty of other parts that were parts of my body before t and that remain parts of it at t.
  7. Here is a better proposal:
      (AP2) If x persists through some finite period leading up to, but not including, t, then, if x exists at t, every set S into which x is decomposable without remainder at t has members with parts that were parts of x before t.
  8. This second assimilation principle seems to me what Hershenov wants and needs. But it is not obviously true; and there is reason to suspect that it is actually violated by objects in our world. At sufficiently small scales, the particles composing the atoms in our bodies behave oddly. Electrons, protons, and neutrons are all fermions, obeying surprising statistical laws that ought to undermine our confidence in their persistence through time. Indistinguishable fermions caught up in the same quantum-mechanical system — for example, all the protons in my body — do not seem "trackable" over time. When plotting the probability of such a system evolving in various ways, one must ignore potential differences in its future states that involve nothing more than the permutation of indistinguishable particles — for example, permutations in which two protons switch places. Why do nature's laws fail to distinguish between circumstance A, in which this proton shows up there and that proton shows up here, and circumstance B, in which that proton shows up there and this proton shows up here? Some say: the best explanation is that the imagined difference between A and B does not exist — these are not two distinct states of the system. If the two protons really persisted over time, A and B would be distinct states; and so the protons do not really persist28.
  9. Since our bodies are interacting with other systems consisting of additional Indistinguishable electrons, protons, and neutrons, one cannot accept this conclusion and straightforwardly affirm that most of the neutrons, protons, and electrons in my body right now were also present in my body moments ago — at least, not if that means they were definitely not present in the other physical objects surrounding me moments ago. At this subatomic level, there seems to be a set S that qualifies as a complete decomposition, without remainder, of my body at t; despite the fact that no members of it are identical with parts of my body prior to t – at least, no members of it are determinately identical with indistinguishable particles constituting my body at earlier times. On this explanation of the puzzling quantum statistics, (AP2) is at least not determinately true.
  10. There are alternative explanations of the strange statistics of subatomic particles. Bohm's version of quantum theory, for example, renders identity of particles through time unproblematic but unknowable. Even without Bohmianism, the statistics may not rule out the possibility of undetectable identity-facts29. Still, why gamble on an assimilation principle that requires the falsehood of an attractive explanation of this strange feature of quantum statistics? My resurrection model is in the clear if the true assimilation principle (whatever it might be) allows for a thing to persist throughout a time leading up to t, despite the fact that, at t, it is completely decomposable into tiny parts, none of which existed prior to t nor had parts that existed prior to t30.
  11. To sum up my response to Hershenov: the Falling Elevator Model may be consistent with a weak assimilation principle for living things, according to which they cannot lose all their proper parts at once — so long as death, for such things, always involves the simultaneous loss of proper parts that could, themselves, survive by the same mechanism. The model will not work if (AP2) is true; but that principle is arguably too strong, probably inconsistent with the persistence of actual living things. What Hershenov needs is an intermediate assimilation principle, one that is weaker than (AP2), but still inconsistent with the resurrection jump. If there is a true principle of this sort, then I expect Hershenov will find it, if anyone can. However, it is not clearly articulated in Hershenov's criticisms so far, which suggest something more like (AP2).

Eric Olson and Discontinuous "Momentum"
  1. In this volume, Eric Olson raises an objection to the idea that tiny particles in my body could carry information about my body's structure into the next world across a spatiotemporal gap. His worry is "not an objection to remote causation in general, or to immanent causation across a spatiotemporal gap, or even to the idea that an atom might cause itself to reappear at a distant time and place without traversing any of the intervening locations31."
  2. It is rather that no such miraculous powers could work together to insure that the atoms appearing in the next world are properly arranged so as to constitute a body just like mine at death. Olson simplifies matters by considering the case of particles that cause themselves to appear at a location not continuous with their current position; but his worries would apply with at least as much force to the "budding" powers needed to implement the Falling Elevator Model:
      How could an object that perishes have the power to reappear at some particular distant location? How could it "find" that place? For an object to cause itself to reappear at a nonrandom location, it would need to have a property analogous to momentum. But the momentum an object has at a given time can only tell it where to be next. It can tell it what direction to move in and how fast. It can't tell it where to be at a time after the object has ceased to have that momentum. … [E]ven if your atoms could reliably find the next world, they could not possibly know where and when to reappear so that the result was a living human being, and not simply a cloud, widely dispersed across space and time. It might happen, perhaps, but it would be fantastically unlikely. It would be like some of the atoms released in an exploding star arranging themselves spontaneously into a living human being. And even if such an event were to get your atoms to the next world arranged as they are now, it wouldn't get you there, as the atoms' organic arrangement would not have been immanently caused by their thisworldly arrangement, but would be an artifact of chance.
  3. Olson grants the possibility of "immanent causation across a spatiotemporal gap"; but then why not grant the possibility of "a property analogous to momentum" that determines where the effect occurs? He seems to think that causation over a gap must be imprecise with respect to the location of the effect, because, during the gap, nothing has the momentum-like property. But I do not see why the momentum-like property needs to continue to be exemplified in order for it to succeed in "pointing to" a specific future location. I shall construct a number of momentum-like properties that could serve to explain why the new particles end up precisely where they do, retaining all of their spatial relations and relative states of motion.
  4. Were we inhabiting a Newtonian substantival space, the trick could easily be managed in any number of ways. Olson is willing to grant that "mnemic causation" is possible — causal relations that hold between temporally distant events, and not in virtue of intervening processes. A temporally gappy causal relationship resembles a ticking time bomb; the cause occurs, and, after a certain interval has passed — long or short, precise or imprecise — the effect occurs. In Newtonian space-time, there are non-relative, precise facts about temporal distances between events; so there is no reason why the ticking time bomb of a mnemic causal relationship could not be perfectly precise. The atoms in my body could, for instance, cause the appearance of duplicate atoms precisely six billion years from the instant at which they are given this power. Again, assuming Newton's absolute space, the atoms could cause more than just the existence of duplicates somewhere in space at that precise time. Let every atom in my body, at my death, be given the power to cause a duplicate to appear at a precise temporal interval in exactly the same part of absolute space it then occupies, and in exactly the same state of motion relative to space. Of course God would have to insure that, in the next world, the parts of space we occupy at our deaths remain habitable, or else be prepared to whisk us out of harm's way as soon as we reappear. A speculative geography of the next world could no doubt be concocted so as to allow for our reappearance by this means, in suitable surroundings.
  5. Momentum-like properties can also be constructed in the Minkowskian space-time of Special Relativity, which includes universe-wide inertial frames that could be used to play the same role as substantival space in the Newtonian context. The Minkowskian manifold lacks Newton's frame-independent facts about the number of years or miles between spatiotemporally separated locations. But for every pair of locations, there are frame-relative facts about such distances; and one frame might be particularly relevant to the powers of atoms in a dying body, so that they duplicate themselves at a precise temporal distance (relative to that frame) in the same state of motion (relative to that frame). One version of this approach would make the same inertial frame relevant to all dying bodies. Perhaps God has already chosen a frame to be the "rest frame of the New Jerusalem", and our bodies are given the power to appear after a certain number of years, as years are measured by clocks in the New Jerusalem; and in the same state of motion they were in at death, relative to the rest frame to be occupied by the Holy City. Another possibility would be that the relevant frame for each body is determined by its own state of motion at death — for example, by its center of mass.
  6. In General Relativity, however, it becomes trickier to cook up spatial and temporal components of a momentum-like property that will do the job — a property that will send the duplicate particles to a particular place in the future, arranged so as to form a resuscitable body then, and arranged thus because of their current arrangement. The space-time of a General Relativistic universe not only lacks privileged sameness of place over time, it also lacks the sort of global inertial frames that I appealed to in the Minkowskian setting (at least, it has no such frames so long as it has any material contents at all). One possibility worth considering is that there is one "timer" that sets the same deadline for all instances of effects produced by mnemic causation. The power to generate duplicate atoms could, for example, be a power to cause them to appear somewhere within a single future space-like slice — say, a slice in which a dramatic universe-wide event occurs as a massive overhaul of the created world. But how could the place and time of my death be matched up with a particular location within such a slice, in such a way that each of the atoms in my body is pointed toward an appropriate subregion of the new location, resulting in a duplication of my body's dying structure?
  7. One might be tempted to posit extra dimensions — beyond the four dimensions of a standard space-time manifold — in which paths link the locations of my particles at death to locations later on; these higher-dimensional paths could be constructed so as to insure that the later locations stand in the same geometrical relations as locations of particles in my dying body. But one might instead rethink the idea that individual atoms (or smaller particles) are given independent replicating powers. If each atom produces a duplicate atom based on an independent power, their powers need to be precisely coordinated, lest the atoms generate nothing more than a next-worldly cloud, just as Olson says. But suppose the miraculous powers to generate new matter are given, not directly to atoms or to the states of individual atoms, but to the quantum state of all the fermions and bosons in my body, say. In that case, their arrangement here and now causes two subsequent arrangements: a similar (but dead) arrangement of subatomic particles in a contiguous space-time region, and a similar (but rapidly reviving) arrangement triggered by the world-wide event which marks the beginning of the next world. The location at which the resurrected body appears could be an indeterministic matter; each human-shaped quantum system might stand an equal chance of showing up in a given region at the magic moment.

Conclusion
  1. I do not wish to rely upon the Falling Elevator Model as a mechanism for my survival. Like the Apostle Paul, I trust that one can be absent from the body yet present with the Lord, even before a general resurrection returns us all to a more natural, embodied state. But I should also like to say that, in the resurrection God secures the continued life of this very body. The Falling Elevator Model may not be the only way God could do so, short of body-snatching; but I still believe it to be one way, despite my critics32.


COMMENT:




In-Page Footnotes ("Zimmerman (Dean) - Bodily Resurrection: The Falling Elevator Model Revisited")

Footnote 1: From the Introduction by Georg Gasser.

Footnote 2: See Peter van Inwagen, "The Possibility of Resurrection", International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 9 (1978): pp. 1 14-21, reprinted in Paul Edwards (ed.), Immortality (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1997), pp. 242-6.
… See "Van Inwagen (Peter) - The Possibility of Resurrection".


Footnote 3: Michael Murray, "Coercion and the Hiddenness of God", American Philosophical Quarterly, 30 (1993): pp. 27-38.

Footnote 4: This possibility is mentioned by van Inwagen; see his The Possibility of Resurrection and Other Essays in Christian Apologetics (Boulder, CO: Westview Press., 1998), p. 49.

Footnote 5: Dean Zimmerman, "The Compatibility of Materialism and Survival: The "Falling Elevator" Model", Faith and Philosophy, 16 (1999): pp. 194-212. A shortened version appeared as Dean Zimmerman, "Materialism and Survival", in Eleonore Stump and Michael Murray (eds), Philosophy of Religion: The Big Questions (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998), pp. 379-86.

Footnote 6: See Hud Hudson, A Materialist Metaphysics of the Human Person (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2001), ch. 7
… See "Hudson (Hud) - Nothing But Dust and Ashes",
and Kevin Corcoran, "Physical Persons and Postmortem Survival without Temporal Gaps", in Corcoran (ed.), Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 2001), pp. 201-17.
… See "Corcoran (Kevin) - Physical Persons and Postmortem Survival Without Temporal Gaps".


Footnote 7: For the details of van lnwagen's materialism, see Peter van Inwagen, Material Beings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University, 1990), esp. ch. 14.
… See "Van Inwagen (Peter) - Material Beings",
… Especially "Van Inwagen (Peter) - The Identities of Material Objects".

Footnote 8: van Inwagen, Christian Apologetics, p. 50.

Footnote 9: William Hasker has done much to develop and defend such a view; see William Hasker, The Emergent Self (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999) and earlier writings.

Footnote 10: See Dean Zimmerman, "Material People", in Michael Loux and Dean Zimmerman Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 491-526,
… See "Zimmerman (Dean) - Material People"
and Dean Zimmerman, "From Property Dualism to Substance Dualism", Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 85: (2010), pp. 119-50.


Footnote 11: See Dean Zimmerman, "Should a Christian Be a Mind-Body Dualist?", in M. Peterson and R. Van Arragon (eds), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (Malden, MA: Basil Blackwell, 2004), pp. 315 27.
… See "Zimmerman (Dean) - Christians Should Affirm Mind-Body Dualism"

Footnote 12: In Zimmerman, "Falling Elevator", pp. 207-9, I anticipated objections from philosophers who doubt that ordinary matter could be given extraordinary causal powers allowing it to jump spatiotemporal gaps; for such philosophers, I proposed an alternative form of direct causal dependency that does not go by way of powers given to the bits of matter themselves, but depends upon a certain kind of divine decree.

Footnote 13: See Hasker, pp. 230-1, esp. p. 230, fn. 64, where he refers the reader to Harold Noonan, Personal Identity (London and New York: Routledge, 1989). See also Hasker, p. 220, fn. 40.
… See "Noonan (Harold) - Personal Identity"

Footnote 14: Hasker, p. 230.

Footnote 15: Noonan, pp. 153-4.
… See "Noonan (Harold) - Quasi-Memory"

Footnote 16: van Inwagen, Material Beings, pp. 202-12.
… See "Van Inwagen (Peter) - Material Beings"

Footnote 17: Zimmerman, "Falling Elevator", pp. 199-200.

Footnote 18: Hasker, p. 229, proposes that "we accept as data" that fission would end Mark's life, but destruction of half Mark's parts could result in his survival.

Footnote 19: Ibid., p. 230.

Footnote 20: Hasker, p. 230.

Footnote 21: Ibid., p. 221 and pp. 230-1.

Footnote 22: Ibid., p. 221, fn. 40, and p. 230, fn. 64.

Footnote 23: Noonan describes a couple of ways to maintain a closest continuer theory while holding onto the necessity of identity, including this one. See Noonan, pp. 157-8.
… See "Noonan (Harold) - Quasi-Memory"

Footnote 24: Hasker directs us to consult Noonan, ch. 7.
… See "Noonan (Harold) - The Reduplication Problem"?

Footnote 25: Hershenov raises another problem: "[s]ince the corpse is the same size as the being that was dying, if it is a result of fission, then half of its matter is new" (David Hershenov, ‘Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection', Religious Studies, 38 (2002): pp. 451-69, p. 462).
… See "Hershenov (David) - Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection"
But that is not true on the official, final version of my Model: all of the new matter is in the resurrected body, none of it in the corpse (Zimmerman, "Falling Elevator", p. 206). Hershenov's main objection has this version as its target.


Footnote 26: Ibid., p. 462.
… See "Hershenov (David) - Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection"

Footnote 27: Ibid., pp. 462-3.
… See "Hershenov (David) - Van Inwagen, Zimmerman, and the Materialist Conception of Resurrection"

Footnote 28: For discussion, see Michael Redhead and Paul Teller, "Particle Labels & the Theory Of Indistinguishable Particles in Quantum Mechanics", British Journal of the Philosophy of Science , 43 (1992): pp. 201-18, and Nick Huggett, "Identity, Quantum Mechanics and Common Sense", The Monist, 80 (1997): pp. 118-30.

Footnote 29: See Simon Saunders, "Are Quantum Particles Objects?", Analysis, 66 (2006): pp.52-63.
… See "Saunders (Simon) - Are Quantum Particles Objects?"

Footnote 30: Note that, so long as there are facts of the matter about atom and molecule identity, the Falling Elevator Model still has a job to do: a mode of resurrection that does not leave the very atoms and molecules in my body behind, to compose a corpse, would still constitute body-snatching.

Footnote 31: Eric Olson's article in this volume (Chapter 3).
… See "Olson (Eric) - Immanent Causation and Life After Death"

Footnote 32: I am grateful to David Hershenov for saving me from a serious mistake in my discussion of assimilation principles



Text Colour Conventions (see disclaimer)
  1. Blue: Text by me; © Theo Todman, 2017
  2. Mauve: Text by correspondent(s) or other author(s); © the author(s)



© Theo Todman, June 2007 - October 2017. Please address any comments on this page to theo@theotodman.com. File output:
Website Maintenance Dashboard
Return to Top of this Page Return to Theo Todman's Philosophy Page Return to Theo Todman's Home Page